
Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl (/ˈhʊsɜːrl/ HUUSS-url,US also /ˈhʊsərəl/ HUUSS-ər-əl;German: [ˈɛtmʊnt ˈhʊsɐl]; 8 April 1859 – 27 April 1938) was an Austrian-German philosopher and mathematician who established the school of phenomenology.
Edmund Husserl | |
---|---|
![]() Husserl c. 1910s | |
Born | Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl 8 April 1859 Proßnitz, Moravia, Austrian Empire |
Died | 27 April 1938 Freiburg, Germany | (aged 79)
Academic background | |
Education |
|
Signature | |
![]() |
In his early work, he elaborated critiques of historicism and of psychologism in logic based on analyses of intentionality. In his mature work, he sought to develop a systematic foundational science based on the so-called phenomenological reduction. Arguing that transcendental consciousness sets the limits of all possible knowledge, Husserl redefined phenomenology as a transcendental-idealist philosophy. Husserl's thought profoundly influenced 20th-century philosophy, and he remains a notable figure in contemporary philosophy and beyond.
Husserl studied mathematics, taught by Karl Weierstrass and Leo Königsberger, and philosophy taught by Franz Brentano and Carl Stumpf. He taught philosophy as a Privatdozent at Halle from 1887, then as professor, first at Göttingen from 1901, then at Freiburg from 1916 until he retired in 1928, after which he remained highly productive. In 1933, under racial laws of the Nazi Party, Husserl was banned from using the library of the University of Freiburg due to his Jewish family background and months later resigned from the Deutsche Akademie. Following an illness, he died in Freiburg in 1938.
Life and career
Youth and education
Husserl was born in 1859 in Proßnitz in the Margraviate of Moravia in the Austrian Empire (today Prostějov in the Czech Republic). He was born into a Jewish family, the second of four children. His father was a milliner. His childhood was spent in Prostějov, where he attended the secular primary school. Then Husserl traveled to Vienna to study at the Realgymnasium there, followed next by the Staatsgymnasium in Olmütz.
At the University of Leipzig from 1876 to 1878, Husserl studied mathematics, physics, and astronomy. At Leipzig, he was inspired by philosophy lectures given by Wilhelm Wundt, one of the founders of modern psychology. Then he moved to the Frederick William University of Berlin (the present-day Humboldt University of Berlin) in 1878 where he continued his study of mathematics under Leopold Kronecker and Karl Weierstrass. In Berlin he found a mentor in Tomáš Garrigue Masaryk, then a former philosophy student of Franz Brentano and later the first president of Czechoslovakia. There Husserl also attended Friedrich Paulsen's philosophy lectures. In 1881 he left for the University of Vienna to complete his mathematics studies under the supervision of Leo Königsberger (a former student of Weierstrass). At Vienna in 1883 he obtained his PhD with the work Beiträge zur Variationsrechnung (Contributions to the Calculus of variations).
Evidently as a result of his becoming familiar with the New Testament during his twenties, Husserl asked to be baptized into the Lutheran Church in 1886. Husserl's father Adolf had died in 1884. Herbert Spiegelberg writes, "While outward religious practice never entered his life any more than it did that of most academic scholars of the time, his mind remained open for the religious phenomenon as for any other genuine experience." At times Husserl saw his goal as one of moral "renewal". Although a steadfast proponent of a radical and rational autonomy in all things, Husserl could also speak "about his vocation and even about his mission under God's will to find new ways for philosophy and science," observes Spiegelberg.
Following his PhD in mathematics, Husserl returned to Berlin to work as the assistant to Karl Weierstrass. Yet already Husserl had felt the desire to pursue philosophy. Then professor Weierstrass became very ill. Husserl became free to return to Vienna where, after serving a short military duty, he devoted his attention to philosophy. In 1884 at the University of Vienna he attended the lectures of Franz Brentano on philosophy and philosophical psychology. Brentano introduced him to the writings of Bernard Bolzano, Hermann Lotze, J. Stuart Mill, and David Hume. Husserl was so impressed by Brentano that he decided to dedicate his life to philosophy; indeed, Franz Brentano is often credited as being his most important influence, e.g., with regard to intentionality. Following academic advice, two years later in 1886 Husserl followed Carl Stumpf, a former student of Brentano, to the University of Halle, seeking to obtain his habilitation which would qualify him to teach at the university level. There, under Stumpf's supervision, he wrote Über den Begriff der Zahl (On the Concept of Number) in 1887, which would serve later as the basis for his first important work, Philosophie der Arithmetik (1891).
In 1887 Husserl married Malvine Steinschneider, a union that would last over fifty years. In 1892 their daughter Elizabeth was born, in 1893 their son Gerhart, and in 1894 their son Wolfgang. Elizabeth would marry in 1922, and Gerhart in 1923; Wolfgang, however, became a casualty of the First World War. Gerhart would become a philosopher of law, contributing to the subject of comparative law, teaching in the United States and after the war in Austria.
Professor of philosophy
Following his marriage Husserl began his long teaching career in philosophy. He started in 1887 as a Privatdozent at the University of Halle. In 1891 he published his Philosophie der Arithmetik. Psychologische und logische Untersuchungen which, drawing on his prior studies in mathematics and philosophy, proposed a psychological context as the basis of mathematics. It drew the adverse notice of Gottlob Frege, who criticized its psychologism.
In 1901 Husserl with his family moved to the University of Göttingen, where he taught as extraordinarius professor. Just prior to this a major work of his, Logische Untersuchungen (Halle, 1900–1901), was published. Volume One contains seasoned reflections on "pure logic" in which he carefully refutes "psychologism". This work was well received and became the subject of a seminar given by Wilhelm Dilthey; Husserl in 1905 traveled to Berlin to visit Dilthey. Two years later in Italy he paid a visit to Franz Brentano, his inspiring old teacher, and to the mathematician Constantin Carathéodory. Kant and Descartes were also now influencing his thought. In 1910 he became joint editor of the journal Logos. During this period Husserl had delivered lectures on internal time consciousness, which several decades later his former students Edith Stein and Martin Heidegger edited for publication.
In 1912 at Freiburg the journal Jahrbuch für Philosophie und Phänomenologische Forschung ("Yearbook for Philosophy and Phenomenological Research") was founded by Husserl and his school, and which published articles of their phenomenological movement from 1913 to 1930. His important work Ideen was published in its first issue (Vol. 1, Issue 1, 1913). Before beginning Ideen, Husserl's thought had reached the stage where "each subject is 'presented' to itself, and to each all others are 'presentiated' (Vergegenwärtigung), not as parts of nature but as pure consciousness".Ideen advanced his transition to a "transcendental interpretation" of phenomenology, a view later criticized by, among others, Jean-Paul Sartre. In Ideen Paul Ricœur sees the development of Husserl's thought as leading "from the psychological cogito to the transcendental cogito". As phenomenology further evolves, it leads (when viewed from another vantage point in Husserl's 'labyrinth') to "transcendental subjectivity". Also in Ideen Husserl explicitly elaborates the phenomenological and eidetic reductions.Ivan Ilyin and Karl Jaspers visited Husserl at Göttingen.
In October 1914 both his sons were sent to fight on the Western Front of World War I, and the following year one of them, Wolfgang Husserl, was badly injured. On 8 March 1916, on the battlefield of Verdun, Wolfgang was killed in action. The next year his other son Gerhart Husserl was wounded in the war but survived. His own mother Julia died. In November 1917 one of his outstanding students and later a noted philosophy professor in his own right, Adolf Reinach, was killed in the war while serving in Flanders.
Husserl had transferred in 1916 to the University of Freiburg (in Freiburg im Breisgau) where he continued bringing his work in philosophy to fruition, now as a full professor.Edith Stein served as his personal assistant during his first few years in Freiburg, followed later by Martin Heidegger from 1920 to 1923. The mathematician Hermann Weyl began corresponding with him in 1918. Husserl gave four lectures on Phenomenological method at University College London in 1922. The University of Berlin in 1923 called on him to relocate there, but he declined the offer. In 1926 Heidegger dedicated his book Sein und Zeit (Being and Time) to him "in grateful respect and friendship." Husserl remained in his professorship at Freiburg until he requested retirement, teaching his last class on 25 July 1928. A Festschrift to celebrate his seventieth birthday was presented to him on 8 April 1929.
Despite retirement, Husserl gave several notable lectures. The first, at Paris in 1929, led to Méditations cartésiennes (Paris 1931). Husserl here reviews the phenomenological epoché (or phenomenological reduction), presented earlier in his pivotal Ideen (1913), in terms of a further reduction of experience to what he calls a 'sphere of ownness.' From within this sphere, which Husserl enacts to show the impossibility of solipsism, the transcendental ego finds itself always already paired with the lived body of another ego, another monad. This 'a priori' interconnection of bodies, given in perception, is what founds the interconnection of consciousnesses known as transcendental intersubjectivity, which Husserl would go on to describe at length in volumes of unpublished writings. There has been a debate over whether or not Husserl's description of ownness and its movement into intersubjectivity is sufficient to reject the charge of solipsism, to which Descartes, for example, was subject. One argument against Husserl's description works this way: instead of infinity and the Deity being the ego's gateway to the Other, as in Descartes, Husserl's ego in the Cartesian Meditations itself becomes transcendent. It remains, however, alone (unconnected). Only the ego's grasp "by analogy" of the Other (e.g., by conjectural reciprocity) allows the possibility for an 'objective' intersubjectivity, and hence for community.
In 1933, the racial laws of the new National Socialist German Workers Party were enacted. On 6 April Husserl was banned from using the library at the University of Freiburg, or any other academic library; the following week, after a public outcry, he was reinstated. Yet his colleague Heidegger was elected Rector of the university on 21–22 April, and joined the Nazi Party. By contrast, in July Husserl resigned from the Deutsche Akademie.
Later Husserl lectured at Prague in 1935 and Vienna in 1936, which resulted in a very differently styled work that, while innovative, is no less problematic: Die Krisis (Belgrade 1936). Husserl describes here the cultural crisis gripping Europe, then approaches a philosophy of history, discussing Galileo, Descartes, several British philosophers, and Kant. The apolitical Husserl before had specifically avoided such historical discussions, pointedly preferring to go directly to an investigation of consciousness. Merleau-Ponty and others question whether Husserl here does not undercut his own position, in that Husserl had attacked in principle historicism, while specifically designing his phenomenology to be rigorous enough to transcend the limits of history. On the contrary, Husserl may be indicating here that historical traditions are merely features given to the pure ego's intuition, like any other. A longer section follows on the "lifeworld" [Lebenswelt], one not observed by the objective logic of science, but a world seen through subjective experience. Yet a problem arises similar to that dealing with 'history' above, a chicken-and-egg problem. Does the lifeworld contextualize and thus compromise the gaze of the pure ego, or does the phenomenological method nonetheless raise the ego up transcendent? These last writings presented the fruits of his professional life. Since his university retirement Husserl had "worked at a tremendous pace, producing several major works."
After suffering a fall in the autumn of 1937, the philosopher became ill with pleurisy. Edmund Husserl died in Freiburg on 27 April 1938, having just turned 79. His wife Malvine survived him. Eugen Fink, his research assistant, delivered his eulogy.Gerhard Ritter was the only Freiburg faculty member to attend the funeral, as an anti-Nazi protest.
Heidegger and the Nazi era
Husserl was rumoured to have been denied the use of the library at Freiburg as a result of the anti-Jewish legislation of April 1933. Relatedly, among other disabilities, Husserl was unable to publish his works in Nazi Germany [see above footnote to Die Krisis (1936)]. It was also rumoured that his former pupil Martin Heidegger informed Husserl that he was discharged, but it was actually the previous rector. Apparently Husserl and Heidegger had moved apart during the 1920s, which became clearer after 1928 when Husserl retired and Heidegger succeeded to his university chair. In the summer of 1929 Husserl had studied carefully selected writings of Heidegger, coming to the conclusion that on several of their key positions they differed: e.g., Heidegger substituted Dasein ["Being-there"] for the pure ego, thus transforming phenomenology into an anthropology, a type of psychologism strongly disfavored by Husserl. Such observations of Heidegger, along with a critique of Max Scheler, were put into a lecture Husserl gave to various Kant Societies in Frankfurt, Berlin, and Halle during 1931 entitled Phänomenologie und Anthropologie.
In the war-time 1941 edition of Heidegger's primary work, Being and Time (Sein und Zeit, first published in 1927), the original dedication to Husserl was removed. This was not due to a negation of the relationship between the two philosophers, however, but rather was the result of a suggested censorship by Heidegger's publisher who feared that the book might otherwise be banned by the Nazi regime. The dedication can still be found in a footnote on page 38, thanking Husserl for his guidance and generosity. Husserl had died three years earlier. In post-war editions of Sein und Zeit the dedication to Husserl is restored. The complex, troubled, and sundered philosophical relationship between Husserl and Heidegger has been widely discussed.
On 4 May 1933, Professor Edmund Husserl addressed the recent regime change in Germany and its consequences:
The future alone will judge which was the true Germany in 1933, and who were the true Germans—those who subscribe to the more or less materialistic-mythical racial prejudices of the day, or those Germans pure in heart and mind, heirs to the great Germans of the past whose tradition they revere and perpetuate.
After his death, Husserl's manuscripts, amounting to approximately 40,000 pages of "Gabelsberger" stenography and his complete research library, were in 1939 smuggled to the Catholic University of Leuven in Belgium by the Franciscan priest Herman Van Breda. There they were deposited at Leuven to form the Husserl-Archives of the Higher Institute of Philosophy. Much of the material in his research manuscripts has since been published in the Husserliana critical edition series.
Development of his thought
Several early themes
In his first works, Husserl combined mathematics, psychology, and philosophy with the goal of providing a sound foundation for mathematics. He analyzed the psychological process needed to obtain the concept of number and then built up a theory on this analysis. He used methods and concepts taken from his teachers. From Weierstrass he derived the idea of generating the concept of number by counting a certain collection of objects. From Brentano and Stumpf he took the distinction between proper and improper presenting.: 159 In an example, Husserl explained this in the following way: if someone is standing in front of a house, they have a proper, direct presentation of that house, but if they are looking for it and ask for directions, then these directions (e.g. the house on the corner of this and that street) are an indirect, improper presentation. In other words, the person can have a proper presentation of an object if it is actually present, and an improper (or symbolic, as Husserl also calls it) one if they only can indicate that object through signs, symbols, etc. Husserl's Logical Investigations (1900–1901) is considered the starting point for the formal theory of wholes and their parts known as mereology.
Another important element that Husserl took over from Brentano was intentionality, the notion that the main characteristic of consciousness is that it is always intentional. While often simplistically summarised as "aboutness" or the relationship between mental acts and the external world, Brentano defined it as the main characteristic of mental phenomena, by which they could be distinguished from physical phenomena. Every mental phenomenon, every psychological act, has a content, is directed at an object (the intentional object). Every belief, desire, etc. has an object that it is about: the believed, the wanted. Brentano used the expression "intentional inexistence" to indicate the status of the objects of thought in the mind. The property of being intentional, of having an intentional object, was the key feature to distinguish mental phenomena and physical phenomena, because physical phenomena lack intentionality altogether.
The elaboration of phenomenology
Some years after the 1900–1901 publication of his main work, the Logische Untersuchungen (Logical Investigations), Husserl made some key conceptual elaborations which led him to assert that to study the structure of consciousness, one would have to distinguish between the act of consciousness and the phenomena at which it is directed (the objects as intended). Knowledge of essences would only be possible by "bracketing" all assumptions about the existence of an external world. This procedure he called "epoché". These new concepts prompted the publication of the Ideen (Ideas) in 1913, in which they were at first incorporated, and a plan for a second edition of the Logische Untersuchungen.
From the Ideen onward, Husserl concentrated on the ideal, essential structures of consciousness. The metaphysical problem of establishing the reality of what people perceive, as distinct from the perceiving subject, was of little interest to Husserl in spite of his being a transcendental idealist. Husserl proposed that the world of objects—and of ways in which people direct themselves toward and perceive those objects—is normally conceived of in what he called the "natural attitude", which is characterized by a belief that objects exist distinct from the perceiving subject and exhibit properties that people see as emanating from them (this attitude is also called physicalist objectivism). Husserl proposed a radical new phenomenological way of looking at objects by examining how people, in their many ways of being intentionally directed toward them, actually "constitute" them (to be distinguished from materially creating objects or objects merely being figments of the imagination); in the Phenomenological standpoint, the object ceases to be something simply "external" and ceases to be seen as providing indicators about what it is, and becomes a grouping of perceptual and functional aspects that imply one another under the idea of a particular object or "type". The notion of objects as real is not expelled by phenomenology, but "bracketed" as a way in which people regard objects—instead of a feature that inheres in an object's essence founded in the relation between the object and the perceiver. To better understand the world of appearances and objects, phenomenology attempts to identify the invariant features of how objects are perceived and pushes attributions of reality into their role as an attribution about the things people perceive (or an assumption underlying how people perceive objects). The major dividing line in Husserl's thought is the turn to transcendental idealism.
In a later period, Husserl began to wrestle with the complicated issues of intersubjectivity, specifically, how communication about an object can be assumed to refer to the same ideal entity (Cartesian Meditations, Meditation V). Husserl tries new methods of bringing his readers to understand the importance of phenomenology to scientific inquiry (and specifically to psychology) and what it means to "bracket" the natural attitude. The Crisis of the European Sciences is Husserl's unfinished work that deals most directly with these issues. In it, Husserl for the first time attempts a historical overview of the development of Western philosophy and science, emphasizing the challenges presented by their increasingly one-sidedly empirical and naturalistic orientation. Husserl declares that mental and spiritual reality possess their own reality independent of any physical basis, and that a science of the mind ('Geisteswissenschaft') must be established on as scientific a foundation as the natural sciences have managed: "It is my conviction that intentional phenomenology has for the first time made spirit as spirit the field of systematic scientific experience, thus effecting a total transformation of the task of knowledge."
Husserl's thought
Husserl's thought is revolutionary in several ways, most notably in the distinction between "natural" and "phenomenological" modes of understanding. In the former, sense-perception in correspondence with the material realm constitutes the known reality, and understanding is premised on the accuracy of the perception and the objective knowability of what is called the "real world". Phenomenological understanding strives to be rigorously "presuppositionless" by means of what Husserl calls "phenomenological reduction". This reduction is not conditioned but rather transcendental: in Husserl's terms, pure consciousness of absolute Being. In Husserl's work, consciousness of any given thing calls for discerning its meaning as an "intentional object". Such an object does not simply strike the senses, to be interpreted or misinterpreted by mental reason; it has already been selected and grasped, grasping being an etymological connotation, of percipere, the root of "perceive".
Meaning and object
From Logical Investigations (1900/1901) to Experience and Judgment (published in 1939), Husserl expressed clearly the difference between meaning and object. He identified several different kinds of names. For example, there are names that have the role of properties that uniquely identify an object. Each of these names expresses a meaning and designates the same object. Examples of this are "the victor in Jena" and "the loser in Waterloo", or "the equilateral triangle" and "the equiangular triangle"; in both cases, both names express different meanings, but designate the same object. There are names which have no meaning, but have the role of designating an object: "Aristotle", "Socrates", and so on. Finally, there are names which designate a variety of objects. These are called "universal names"; their meaning is a "concept" and refers to a series of objects (the extension of the concept). The way people know sensible objects is called "sensible intuition".
Husserl also identifies a series of "formal words" which are necessary to form sentences and have no sensible correlates. Examples of formal words are "a", "the", "more than", "over", "under", "two", "group", and so on. Every sentence must contain formal words to designate what Husserl calls "formal categories". There are two kinds of categories: meaning categories and formal-ontological categories. Meaning categories relate judgments; they include forms of conjunction, disjunction, forms of plural, among others. Formal-ontological categories relate objects and include notions such as set, cardinal number, ordinal number, part and whole, relation, and so on. The way people know these categories is through a faculty of understanding called "categorial intuition".
Through sensible intuition, consciousness constitutes what Husserl calls a "situation of affairs" (Sachlage). It is a passive constitution where objects themselves are presented. To this situation of affairs, through categorial intuition, people are able to constitute a "state of affairs" (Sachverhalt). One situation of affairs through objective acts of consciousness (acts of constituting categorially) can serve as the basis for constituting multiple states of affairs. For example, suppose a and b are two sensible objects in a certain situation of affairs. It can be used as the basis to say, "a<b" and "b>a", two judgments which designate the same state of affairs. For Husserl a sentence has a proposition or judgment as its meaning, and refers to a state of affairs which has a situation of affairs as a reference base.: 35
Formal and regional ontology
Husserl sees ontology as a science of essences.Sciences of essences are contrasted with factual sciences: the former are knowable a priori and provide the foundation for the later, which are knowable a posteriori. Ontology as a science of essences is not interested in actual facts, but in the essences themselves, whether they have instances or not. Husserl distinguishes between formal ontology, which investigates the essence of objectivity in general, and regional ontologies, which study regional essences that are shared by all entities belonging to the region. Regions correspond to the highest genera of concrete entities: material nature, personal consciousness and interpersonal spirit. Husserl's method for studying ontology and sciences of essence in general is called eidetic variation. It involves imagining an object of the kind under investigation and varying its features. The changed feature is inessential to this kind if the object can survive its change, otherwise it belongs to the kind's essence. For example, a triangle remains a triangle if one of its sides is extended but it ceases to be a triangle if a fourth side is added. Regional ontology involves applying this method to the essences corresponding to the highest genera.
Philosophy of logic and mathematics
Husserl believed that truth-in-itself has as ontological correlate being-in-itself, just as meaning categories have formal-ontological categories as correlates. Logic is a formal theory of judgment, that studies the formal a priori relations among judgments using meaning categories. Mathematics, on the other hand, is formal ontology; it studies all the possible forms of being (of objects). Hence for both logic and mathematics, the different formal categories are the objects of study, not the sensible objects themselves. The problem with the psychological approach to mathematics and logic is that it fails to account for the fact that this approach is about formal categories, and not simply about abstractions from sensibility alone. The reason why sensible objects are not dealt with in mathematics is because of another faculty of understanding called "categorial abstraction." Through this faculty people are able to get rid of sensible components of judgments, and just focus on formal categories themselves.
Thanks to "eidetic reduction" (or "essential intuition"), people are able to grasp the possibility, impossibility, necessity and contingency among concepts and among formal categories. Categorial intuition, along with categorial abstraction and eidetic reduction, are the basis for logical and mathematical knowledge.
Husserl criticized the logicians of his day for not focusing on the relation between subjective processes that offer objective knowledge of pure logic. All subjective activities of consciousness need an ideal correlate, and objective logic (constituted noematically) as it is constituted by consciousness needs a noetic correlate (the subjective activities of consciousness).
Husserl stated that logic has three strata, each further away from consciousness and psychology than those that precede it.
- The first stratum is what Husserl called a "morphology of meanings" concerning a priori ways to relate judgments to make them meaningful. In this stratum people elaborate a "pure grammar" or a logical syntax, and he would call its rules "laws to prevent non-sense", which would be similar to what logic calls today "formation rules". Mathematics, as logic's ontological correlate, also has a similar stratum, a "morphology of formal-ontological categories".
- The second stratum would be called by Husserl "logic of consequence" or the "logic of non-contradiction" which explores all possible forms of true judgments. He includes here syllogistic classic logic, propositional logic and that of predicates. This is a semantic stratum, and the rules of this stratum would be the "laws to avoid counter-sense" or "laws to prevent contradiction". They are very similar to today's logic "transformation rules". Mathematics also has a similar stratum which is based among others on pure theory of pluralities, and a pure theory of numbers. They provide a science of the conditions of possibility of any theory whatsoever. Husserl also talked about what he called "logic of truth" which consists of the formal laws of possible truth and its modalities, and precedes the third logical third stratum.
- The third stratum is metalogical, what he called a "theory of all possible forms of theories." It explores all possible theories in an a priori fashion, rather than the possibility of theory in general. Theories of possible relations between pure forms of theories could be established; these logical relations could in turn be investigated using deduction. The logician is free to see the extension of this deductive, theoretical sphere of pure logic.
The ontological correlate to the third stratum is the "theory of manifolds". In formal ontology, it is a free investigation where a mathematician can assign several meanings to several symbols, and all their possible valid deductions in a general and indeterminate manner. It is, properly speaking, the most universal mathematics of all. Through the posit of certain indeterminate objects (formal-ontological categories) as well as any combination of mathematical axioms, mathematicians can explore the apodeictic connections between them, as long as consistency is preserved.
According to Husserl, this view of logic and mathematics accounted for the objectivity of a series of mathematical developments of his time, such as n-dimensional manifolds (both Euclidean and non-Euclidean), Hermann Grassmann's theory of extensions, William Rowan Hamilton's Hamiltonians, Sophus Lie's theory of transformation groups, and Cantor's set theory.
Jacob Klein was one student of Husserl who pursued this line of inquiry, seeking to "desedimentize" mathematics and the mathematical sciences.
Husserl and psychologism
Philosophy of arithmetic and Frege
After obtaining his PhD in mathematics, Husserl began analyzing the foundations of mathematics from a psychological point of view. In his habilitation thesis, On the Concept of Number (1886) and in his Philosophy of Arithmetic (1891), Husserl sought, by employing Brentano's descriptive psychology, to define the natural numbers in a way that advanced the methods and techniques of Karl Weierstrass, Richard Dedekind, Georg Cantor, Gottlob Frege, and other contemporary mathematicians. Later, in the first volume of his Logical Investigations, the Prolegomena of Pure Logic, Husserl, while attacking the psychologistic point of view in logic and mathematics, also appears to reject much of his early work, although the forms of psychologism analysed and refuted in the Prolegomena did not apply directly to his Philosophy of Arithmetic. Some scholars question whether Frege's negative review of the Philosophy of Arithmetic helped turn Husserl towards modern Platonism, but he had already discovered the work of Bernard Bolzano independently around 1890/91. In his Logical Investigations, Husserl explicitly mentioned Bolzano, G. W. Leibniz and Hermann Lotze as inspirations for his newer position.
Husserl's review of Ernst Schröder, published before Frege's landmark 1892 article, clearly distinguishes sense from reference; thus Husserl's notions of noema and object also arose independently. Likewise, in his criticism of Frege in the Philosophy of Arithmetic, Husserl remarks on the distinction between the content and the extension of a concept. Moreover, the distinction between the subjective mental act, namely the content of a concept, and the (external) object, was developed independently by Brentano and his school, and may have surfaced as early as Brentano's 1870s lectures on logic.
Scholars such as J. N. Mohanty, Claire Ortiz Hill, and , among others, have argued that Husserl's so-called change from psychologism to Platonism came about independently of Frege's review.: 253–262 For example, the review falsely accuses Husserl of subjectivizing everything, so that no objectivity is possible, and falsely attributes to him a notion of abstraction whereby objects disappear until all that remains are numbers as mere ghosts.[citation needed] Contrary to what Frege states, in Husserl's Philosophy of Arithmetic there are already two different kinds of representations: subjective and objective. Moreover, objectivity is clearly defined in that work. Frege's attack seems to be directed at certain foundational doctrines then current in Weierstrass's Berlin School, of which Husserl and Cantor cannot be said to be orthodox representatives.
Furthermore, various sources indicate that Husserl changed his mind about psychologism as early as 1890, a year before he published the Philosophy of Arithmetic. Husserl stated that by the time he published that book, he had already changed his mind—that he had doubts about psychologism from the very outset. He attributed this change of mind to his reading of Leibniz, Bolzano, Lotze, and David Hume. Husserl makes no mention of Frege as a decisive factor in this change. In his Logical Investigations, Husserl mentions Frege only twice, once in a footnote to point out that he had retracted three pages of his criticism of Frege's The Foundations of Arithmetic, and again to question Frege's use of the word Bedeutung to designate "reference" rather than "meaning" (sense).
In a letter dated 24 May 1891, Frege thanked Husserl for sending him a copy of the Philosophy of Arithmetic and Husserl's review of Ernst Schröder's Vorlesungen über die Algebra der Logik. In the same letter, Frege used the review of Schröder's book to analyze Husserl's notion of the sense of reference of concept words. Hence Frege recognized, as early as 1891, that Husserl distinguished between sense and reference. Consequently, Frege and Husserl independently elaborated a theory of sense and reference before 1891.
Commentators argue that Husserl's notion of noema has nothing to do with Frege's notion of sense, because noemata are necessarily fused with noeses which are the conscious activities of consciousness. Noemata have three different levels:
- The substratum, which is never presented to the consciousness, and is the support of all the properties of the object;
- The noematic senses, which are the different ways the objects are presented to us;
- The modalities of being (possible, doubtful, existent, non-existent, absurd, and so on).
Consequently, in intentional activities, even non-existent objects can be constituted, and form part of the whole noema. Frege, however, did not conceive of objects as forming parts of senses: If a proper name denotes a non-existent object, it does not have a reference, hence concepts with no objects have no truth value in arguments. Moreover, Husserl did not maintain that predicates of sentences designate concepts. According to Frege the reference of a sentence is a truth value; for Husserl it is a "state of affairs." Frege's notion of "sense" is unrelated to Husserl's noema, while the latter's notions of "meaning" and "object" differ from those of Frege.
In detail, Husserl's conception of logic and mathematics differs from that of Frege, who held that arithmetic could be derived from logic. For Husserl this is not the case: mathematics (with the exception of geometry) is the ontological correlate of logic, and while both fields are related, neither one is strictly reducible to the other.
Husserl's criticism of psychologism
Reacting against authors such as John Stuart Mill, Christoph von Sigwart and his own former teacher Brentano, Husserl criticised their psychologism in mathematics and logic, i.e. their conception of these abstract and a priori sciences as having an essentially empirical foundation and a prescriptive or descriptive nature. According to psychologism, logic would not be an autonomous discipline, but a branch of psychology, either proposing a prescriptive and practical "art" of correct judgement (as Brentano and some of his more orthodox students did) or a description of the factual processes of human thought. Husserl pointed out that the failure of anti-psychologists to defeat psychologism was a result of being unable to distinguish between the foundational, theoretical side of logic, and the applied, practical side. Pure logic does not deal at all with "thoughts" or "judgings" as mental episodes but about a priori laws and conditions for any theory and any judgments whatsoever, conceived as propositions in themselves.
- "Here 'Judgement' has the same meaning as 'proposition', understood, not as a grammatical, but as an ideal unity of meaning. This is the case with all the distinctions of acts or forms of judgement, which provide the foundations for the laws of pure logic. Categorial, hypothetical, disjunctive, existential judgements, and however else we may call them, in pure logic are not names for classes of judgements, but for ideal forms of propositions."
Since "truth-in-itself" has "being-in-itself" as ontological correlate, and since psychologists reduce truth (and hence logic) to empirical psychology, the inevitable consequence is scepticism. Psychologists have not been successful either in showing how induction or psychological processes can justify the absolute certainty of logical principles, such as the principles of identity and non-contradiction. It is therefore futile to base certain logical laws and principles on uncertain processes of the mind.
This confusion made by psychologism (and related disciplines such as biologism and anthropologism) can be due to three specific prejudices:
- The first prejudice is the supposition that logic is somehow normative in nature. Husserl argues that logic is theoretical, i.e., that logic itself proposes a priori laws which are themselves the basis of the normative side of logic. Since mathematics is related to logic, he cites an example from mathematics: a formula like "(a + b)(a – b) = a² – b²" does not offer any insight into how to think mathematically. It just expresses a truth. A proposition that says: "The product of the sum and the difference of a and b should give the difference of the squares of a and b" does express a normative proposition, but this normative statement is based on the theoretical statement "(a + b)(a – b) = a² – b²".
- For psychologists, the acts of judging, reasoning, deriving, and so on, are all psychological processes. Therefore, it is the role of psychology to provide the foundation of these processes. Husserl states that this effort made by psychologists is a "metábasis eis állo génos" (Ancient Greek: μετάβασις εἰς ἄλλο γένος, lit. 'a transgression to another field').: 344 It is a metábasis because psychology cannot provide any foundations for a priori laws which themselves are the basis for all correct thought. Psychologists have the problem of confusing intentional activities with the object of these activities. It is important to distinguish between the act of judging and the judgment itself, the act of counting and the number itself, and so on. Counting five objects is undeniably a psychological process, but the number 5 is not.
- Judgments can be true or not true. Psychologists argue that judgments are true because they become "evidently" true to us.: 261 This evidence, a psychological process that "guarantees" truth, is indeed a psychological process. Husserl responds by saying that truth itself, as well as logical laws, always remain valid regardless of psychological "evidence" that they are true. No psychological process can explain the a priori objectivity of these logical truths.
From this criticism to psychologism, the distinction between psychological acts and their intentional objects, and the difference between the normative side of logic and the theoretical side, derives from a Platonist conception of logic. This means that logical and mathematical laws should be regarded as being independent of the human mind, and also as an autonomy of meanings. It is essentially the difference between the real (everything subject to time) and the ideal or irreal (everything that is atemporal), such as logical truths, mathematical entities, mathematical truths and meanings in general.
Influence
David Carr commented on Husserl following in his 1970 dissertation at Yale: "It is well known that Husserl was always disappointed at the tendency of his students to go their own way, to embark upon fundamental revisions of phenomenology rather than engage in the communal task" as originally intended by the radical new science. Notwithstanding, he did attract philosophers to phenomenology.
Martin Heidegger is the best known of Husserl's students, the one whom Husserl chose as his successor at Freiburg. Heidegger's magnum opus Being and Time was dedicated to Husserl. They shared their thoughts and worked alongside each other for over a decade at the University of Freiburg, Heidegger being Husserl's assistant during 1920–1923. Heidegger's early work followed his teacher, but with time he began to develop new insights distinctively variant. Husserl became increasingly critical of Heidegger's work, especially in 1929, and included pointed criticism of Heidegger in lectures he gave during 1931. Heidegger, while acknowledging his debt to Husserl, followed a political position offensive and harmful to Husserl after the Nazis came to power in 1933, Husserl being of Jewish origin and Heidegger infamously being then a Nazi proponent. Academic discussion of Husserl and Heidegger is extensive.
At Göttingen in 1913 Adolf Reinach (1884–1917) "was now Husserl's right hand. He was above all the mediator between Husserl and the students, for he understood extremely well how to deal with other persons, whereas Husserl was pretty much helpless in this respect." He was an original editor of Husserl's new journal, Jahrbuch; one of his works (giving a phenomenological analysis of the law of obligations) appeared in its first issue. Reinach was widely admired and a remarkable teacher. Husserl, in his 1917 obituary, wrote, "He wanted to draw only from the deepest sources, he wanted to produce only work of enduring value. And through his wise restraint he succeeded in this."
Edith Stein was Husserl's student at Göttingen and Freiburg while she wrote her doctoral thesis The Empathy Problem as it Developed Historically and Considered Phenomenologically (1916). She then became his assistant at Freiburg in 1916–18. She later adapted her phenomenology to the modern school of modern Thomism.
Ludwig Landgrebe became assistant to Husserl in 1923. From 1939 he collaborated with Eugen Fink at the Husserl-Archives in Leuven. In 1954 he became leader of the Husserl-Archives. Landgrebe is known as one of Husserl's closest associates, but also for his independent views relating to history, religion and politics as seen from the viewpoints of existentialist philosophy and metaphysics.
Eugen Fink was a close associate of Husserl during the 1920s and 1930s. He wrote the Sixth Cartesian Meditation which Husserl said was the truest expression and continuation of his own work. Fink delivered the eulogy for Husserl in 1938.
Roman Ingarden, an early student of Husserl at Freiburg, corresponded with Husserl into the mid-1930s. Ingarden did not accept, however, the later transcendental idealism of Husserl which he thought would lead to relativism. Ingarden has written his work in German and Polish. In his Spór o istnienie świata (Ger.: "Der Streit um die Existenz der Welt", Eng.: "Dispute about existence of the world") he created his own realistic position, which also helped to spread phenomenology in Poland.
Max Scheler met Husserl in Halle in 1901 and found in his phenomenology a methodological breakthrough for his own philosophy. Scheler, who was at Göttingen when Husserl taught there, was one of the original few editors of the journal Jahrbuch für Philosophie und Phänomenologische Forschung (1913). Scheler's work Formalism in Ethics and Nonformal Ethics of Value appeared in the new journal (1913 and 1916) and drew acclaim. The personal relationship between the two men, however, became strained, due to Scheler's legal troubles, and Scheler returned to Munich. Although Scheler later criticised Husserl's idealistic logical approach and proposed instead a "phenomenology of love", he states that he remained "deeply indebted" to Husserl throughout his work.
Nicolai Hartmann was once thought to be at the center of phenomenology, but perhaps no longer. In 1921 the prestige of Hartmann the Neo-Kantian, who was Professor of Philosophy at Marburg, was added to the Movement; he "publicly declared his solidarity with the actual work of die Phänomenologie." Yet Hartmann's connections were with Max Scheler and the Munich circle; Husserl himself evidently did not consider him as a phenomenologist. His philosophy, however, is said to include an innovative use of the method.
Emmanuel Levinas in 1929 gave a presentation at one of Husserl's last seminars in Freiburg. Also that year he wrote on Husserl's Ideen (1913) a long review published by a French journal. With Gabrielle Peiffer, Levinas translated into French Husserl's Méditations cartésiennes (1931). He was at first impressed with Heidegger and began a book on him, but broke off the project when Heidegger became involved with the Nazis. After the war he wrote on Jewish spirituality; most of his family had been murdered by the Nazis in Lithuania. Levinas then began to write works that would become widely known and admired.
Alfred Schutz's Phenomenology of the Social World seeks to rigorously ground Max Weber's interpretive sociology in Husserl's phenomenology. Husserl was impressed by this work and asked Schutz to be his assistant.
Jean-Paul Sartre was also largely influenced by Husserl, although he later came to disagree with key points in his analyses. Sartre rejected Husserl's transcendental interpretations begun in his Ideen (1913) and instead followed Heidegger's ontology.
Maurice Merleau-Ponty's Phenomenology of Perception is influenced by Edmund Husserl's work on perception, intersubjectivity, intentionality, space, and temporality, including Husserl's theory of retention and protention. Merleau-Ponty's description of 'motor intentionality' and sexuality, for example, retain the important structure of the noetic/noematic correlation of Ideen I, yet further concretize what it means for Husserl when consciousness particularizes itself into modes of intuition. Merleau-Ponty's most clearly Husserlian work is, perhaps, "the Philosopher and His Shadow." Depending on the interpretation of Husserl's accounts of eidetic intuition, given in Husserl's Phenomenological Psychology and Experience and Judgment, it may be that Merleau-Ponty did not accept the "eidetic reduction" nor the "pure essence" said to result. Merleau-Ponty was the first student to study at the Husserl-archives in Leuven.
Gabriel Marcel explicitly rejected existentialism, due to Sartre, but not phenomenology, which has enjoyed a wide following among French Catholics. He appreciated Husserl, Scheler, and (but with apprehension) Heidegger. His expressions like "ontology of sensability" when referring to the body, indicate influence by phenomenological thought.
Kurt Gödel is known to have read Cartesian Meditations. He expressed very strong appreciation for Husserl's work, especially with regard to "bracketing" or "epoché".
Hermann Weyl's interest in intuitionistic logic and impredicativity appears to have resulted from his reading of Husserl. He was introduced to Husserl's work through his wife, Helene Joseph, herself a student of Husserl at Göttingen.
Colin Wilson has used Husserl's ideas extensively in developing his "New Existentialism," particularly in regards to his "intentionality of consciousness," which he mentions in a number of his books.
Rudolf Carnap was also influenced by Husserl, not only concerning Husserl's notion of essential insight that Carnap used in his Der Raum, but also his notion of "formation rules" and "transformation rules" is founded on Husserl's philosophy of logic.
Karol Wojtyla, who would later become Pope John Paul II, was influenced by Husserl. Phenomenology appears in his major work, The Acting Person (1969). Originally published in Polish, it was translated by Andrzej Potocki and edited by Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka in the Analecta Husserliana. The Acting Person combines phenomenological work with Thomistic ethics.
Paul Ricœur has translated many works of Husserl into French and has also written many of his own studies of the philosopher. Among other works, Ricœur employed phenomenology in his Freud and Philosophy (1965).
Jacques Derrida wrote several critical studies of Husserl early in his academic career. These included his dissertation, The Problem of Genesis in Husserl's Philosophy, and also his introduction to The Origin of Geometry. Derrida continued to make reference to Husserl in works such as Of Grammatology.
Stanisław Leśniewski and Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz were inspired by Husserl's formal analysis of language. Accordingly, they employed phenomenology in the development of categorial grammar.
José Ortega y Gasset visited Husserl at Freiburg in 1934. He credited phenomenology for having 'liberated him' from a narrow neo-Kantian thought. While perhaps not a phenomenologist himself, he introduced the philosophy to Iberia and Latin America.
Wilfrid Sellars, an influential figure in the so-called "Pittsburgh School" (Robert Brandom, John McDowell) had been a student of Marvin Farber, a pupil of Husserl, and was influenced by phenomenology through him:
Marvin Farber led me through my first careful reading of the Critique of Pure Reason and introduced me to Husserl. His combination of utter respect for the structure of Husserl's thought with the equally firm conviction that this structure could be given a naturalistic interpretation was undoubtedly a key influence on my own subsequent philosophical strategy.
In his 1942 essay The Myth of Sisyphus, absurdist philosopher Albert Camus acknowledges Husserl as a previous philosopher who described and attempted to deal with the feeling of the absurd, but claims he committed "philosophical suicide" by elevating reason and ultimately arriving at ubiquitous Platonic forms and an abstract god.
Hans Blumenberg received his habilitation in 1950, with a dissertation on ontological distance, an inquiry into the crisis of Husserl's phenomenology.
Roger Scruton, despite some disagreements with Husserl, drew upon his work in (1986).: 3–4
The influence of the Husserlian phenomenological tradition in the 21st century extends beyond the confines of the European and North American legacies. It has already started to impact (indirectly) scholarship in Eastern and Oriental thought, including research on the impetus of philosophical thinking in the history of ideas in Islam.
Bibliography
In German
- 1887. Über den Begriff der Zahl. Psychologische Analysen (On the Concept of Number; habilitation thesis)
- 1891. Philosophie der Arithmetik. Psychologische und logische Untersuchungen (Philosophy of Arithmetic)
- 1900. Logische Untersuchungen. Erster Teil: Prolegomena zur reinen Logik (Logical Investigations, Vol. 1: Prolegomena to Pure Logic)
- 1901. Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Teil: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis (Logical Investigations, Vol. 2)
- 1911. Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft (included in Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy: Philosophy as Rigorous Science and Philosophy and the Crisis of European Man)
- 1913. Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie (Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology)
- 1923–24. Erste Philosophie. Zweiter Teil: Theorie der phänomenologischen Reduktion (First Philosophy, Vol. 2: Phenomenological Reductions)
- 1925. Erste Philosophie. Erster Teil: Kritische Ideengeschichte (First Philosophy, Vol. 1: Critical History of Ideas)
- 1928. Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins (Lectures on the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time)
- 1929. Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft (Formal and Transcendental Logic)
- 1930. Nachwort zu meinen "Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie" (Postscript to my "Ideas")
- 1936. Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie: Eine Einleitung in die phänomenologische Philosophie (The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy)
- 1939. Erfahrung und Urteil. Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik. (Experience and Judgment)
- 1950. Cartesianische Meditationen (translation of Méditations cartésiennes (Cartesian Meditations, 1931))
- 1952. Ideen II: Phänomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution (Ideas II: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution)
- 1952. Ideen III: Die Phänomenologie und die Fundamente der Wissenschaften (Ideas III: Phenomenology and the Foundations of the Sciences)
- 1973. Zur Phänomenologie der Intersubjektivität (On the Phenomenology of Intersubjectivity)
In English
- Philosophy of Arithmetic, Willard, Dallas, trans., 2003 [1891]. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Logical Investigations, 1973 [1900, 2nd revised edition 1913], Findlay, J. N., trans. London: Routledge.
- "Philosophy as Rigorous Science", translated in Quentin Lauer, S.J., editor, 1965 [1910] Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy. New York: Harper & Row.
- Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy – First Book: General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology, 1982 [1913]. Kersten, F., trans. The Hague: Nijhoff.
- Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy – Second Book: Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution, 1989. R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer, translators. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy – Third Book: Phenomenology and the Foundations of the Sciences, 1980, Klein, T. E., and Pohl, W. E., translators. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time (1893–1917), 1990 [1928]. Brough, J.B., trans. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Cartesian Meditations, 1960 [1931]. Cairns, D., trans. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Formal and Transcendental Logic, 1969 [1929], Cairns, D., trans. The Hague: Nijhoff.
- Experience and Judgement, 1973 [1939], Churchill, J. S., and Ameriks, K., translators. London: Routledge.
- The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology, 1970 [1936/54], Carr, D., trans. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
- "Universal Teleology". Telos 4 (Fall 1969). New York: Telos Press.
Anthologies
- Willard, Dallas, trans., 1994. Early Writings in the Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
- Welton, Donn, ed., 1999. The Essential Husserl. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
See also
- Early phenomenology
- Experimental phenomenology
- List of phenomenologists
Notes
- Husserl is mentioned by Bernard Stiegler in the 2004 film The Ister.
Citations
-
- "Husserl". Collins English Dictionary. HarperCollins. Retrieved 24 August 2019.
- "Husserl". Dictionary.com.
- "Husserl". The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language (5th ed.). HarperCollins. Retrieved 24 August 2019.
- "Husserl". Merriam-Webster.com Dictionary. Merriam-Webster. Retrieved 24 August 2019.
- Krech, Eva-Maria; Stock, Eberhard; Hirschfeld, Ursula; Anders, Lutz Christian (2009). Deutsches Aussprachewörterbuch [German Pronunciation Dictionary] (in German). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter. pp. 465, 598. ISBN 978-3-11-018202-6.
- Smith, D. W. (2007). Husserl. p. xiv.
- Cooper-Wiele, J. K. (6 December 2012). The Totalizing Act: Key to Husserl's Early Philosophy. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-94-009-2259-4.
- Kockelmans, Joseph J.; Kisiel, Theodore J. (1970). Phenomenology and the Natural Sciences: Essays and Translations. Northwestern University Press. p. 3. ISBN 978-0-8101-0613-0.
- Joseph J. Kockelmans, "Biographical Note" per Edmund Husserl, at 17–20, in his edited Phenomenology. The Philosophy of Edmund Husserl and Its Interpretation (Garden City NY: Doubleday Anchor 1967).
- "Husserl Page: Husserl's Biography in Brief". Husserlpage.com. Retrieved 28 July 2023.
- Spiegelberg, H. The Phenomenological Movement. A historical introduction. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 2d ed. ISBN 9024702399. Vol. I, pp. 85–87. It was reported "from witnesses of Husserl's last days – that Husserl had something like a deathbed conversion." Spiegelberg (1971) at I:85.
- Spiegelberg, E. (9 March 2013). The Context of the Phenomenological Movement. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 134. ISBN 978-94-017-3270-3.
- Kockelmans, "Biographical Note" per Edmund Husserl, 17–20, at 17–18, in his edited Phenomenology (Doubleday Anchor 1967). Husserl's 'Philosophie der Arithmetik is further discussed here below.
- "Gerhart Husserl; by H. Pallard and R. Hudson". Archived from the original on 7 February 2005.
- Cf., "Illustrative extracts from Frege's Review of Husserl's Philosophie der Arithmetik", translated by P.T.Geach, at 79–85, in Peter Geach and Max Black, editors, Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege (Oxford: Basil Blackwell 1977).
- Beyer, Christian (2022), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), "Edmund Husserl", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 26 February 2025,
What the exact impact this criticism by Frege may have had on Husserl's subsequent positions is the subject of debate. See below herein the section "Husserl and the Critique of Psychologism" and the subsection "Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics".
- Husserl's Logische, in its disentangling of psychology from logic, also served as preparation for the later development of his work in phenomenological reduction. Marvin Farber, "Husserl and Philosophical Radicalism. The ideas of a presuppositionless philosophy" 37–57 at 47–48, in Kockelmans, ed., Phenomenology (1967).
- Ricoeur, Paul (December 1967). "29-30". Husserl: An Analysis of His Phenomenology. Northwestern University Press. ISBN 978-0-8101-0530-0.
Ricœur traces Husserl's development from the Logische Untersuchungen to his later Ideen (Ideas, 1913), as leading from the psychological to the transcendental, regarding the intuition of essences (which the methodology of the phenomenological reduction allows). The book Husserl contains translations of Ricœur's essays of 1949–1967.
- Husserl, Vorlesungen zur Phänomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins (1928), translated as The Phenomenology of Internal Time Consciousness (Indiana University 1964).
- Husserl, Ideen au einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie (1913), translated as Ideas. General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology (New York: Macmillan 1931; reprint Collier), with "Author's Preface to the English Edition" at 5–22. Therein, Husserl in 1931 refers to "Transcendental Subjectivity" being "a new field of experience" opened as a result of practicing phenomenological reduction, and giving rise to an a priori science not empirically based but somewhat similar to mathematics. By such practice the individual becomes the "transcendental Ego", although Husserl acknowledges the problem of solipsism. Later he emphasizes "the necessary stressing of the difference between transcendental and psychological subjectivity, the repeated declaration that transcendental phenomenology is not in any sense psychology" but rather (in contrast to naturalistic psychology) by the phenomenological reduction "the life of the soul is made intelligible in its most intimate and originally intuitional essence" and whereby "objects of the most varied grades right up to the level of the objective world are there for the Ego" (Ibid. at 5–7, 11–12, 18).
- Ricoeur, Paul (1967). Husserl. An Analysis of His Phenomenology. p. 33. In his "Ideen period" (1911–1925) Husserl also produced two unpublished manuscripts later referred to as Ideen II and Ideen III. Ricœur (1967) at 35.
- Jean-Paul Sartre, "La Transcendance de L'Ego. Esquisse d'une description phénoménologique" in Recherches Philosophiques, VI (1937), translated as The Transcendence of the Ego. An existentialist theory of consciousness (New York: The Noonday Press 1957). Sartre's "disagreement with Husserl seems to have facilitated the transition from phenomenology to the existentialist doctrines of L'Être et le Néant [1943]." F. Williams and R. Kirkpatrick, "Translator's introduction" 11–27, at 12, to Transcendence of the Ego (1957).
- Ricoeur, Paul (1967). Husserl. An Analysis of His Phenomenology. Northwestern University. pp. 29, 30; cf., 177–178.
- Husserl, Ideen (1913), translated as Ideas (1931), e.g., at 161–165.
- Ricoeur, Husserl (1967) at 25–27. Ideen does not address the problem of solipsism. Ricœur (1967) at 31.
- Peter Koestenbaum, "Introductory Essay" ix–lxxvii, at lxxv, in Husserl, The Paris Lectures (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 2d ed. 1967).
- In the 1962 translation Being and Time by Macquarrie and Robinson, Heidegger states: "Dedicated to Edmund Husserl in friendship and admiration. Todnauberg in Baden, Black Forest, 8 April 1926".
- Edmund Husserl, Pariser Vorträge [1929], translated as The Paris Lectures (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 2d ed. 1967), by Peter Koestenbaum, with an "Introductory Essay" at ix–lxxvii.
- This work was published first in French. Husserl, Méditations cartésiennes (Paris: Armand Colin 1931), translated by Gabrielle Peiffer and Emmanuel Levinas. A German edition Cartesianische Meditationen (which Husserl had reworked) came out in 1950.
- Ricoeur, Paul (1967). Husserl. An Analysis of His Phenomenology. Northwestern University. pp. 82–85, 115–116, 123–142. Ricoeur wonders whether here Husserl does not "square the circle" regarding the issue of solipsism.
- Zack, Naomi (September 2009). The Handy Philosophy Answer Book. Visible Ink Press. pp. 273–274. ISBN 978-1-57859-277-7.
- Husserl, Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phänomenologie (Belgrade 1936). "As a Jew who was denied any public platform in Germany, Husserl had to publish, as he had lectured, outside his own country." Philosophia in Belgrade began its publication. David Carr, "Translator's Introduction" xv–xliii, at xvii, to Edmund Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology (Northwestern University 1970).
- Quentin Lauer, "Introduction", pp. 1–68, at pp. 6–7, in Edmund Husserl, Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy (New York: Harper & Row/Torchbook 1965); translated are two works by Husserl: the 1935 Prague lecture "Philosophy and the Crisis of European Man" [Philosophie und die Krisis des europäischen Menschentums], and the 1911 essay "Philosophy as Rigorous Science" [Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft].
- Carr, David (1970) "Translator's Introduction" xv–xliii, at xxx–xxxi, xxxiv–xxxv, xxxvii–xxxviii (historicism), xxxvi–xxxvii (as given), to Husserl, The Crises of European Sciences.
- Ricœur, Paul (1949) "Husserl et le sens de l'histoire", as translated in his Husserl. An Analysis of His Phenomenology (1967) at pp. 143–174.
- Husserl, The Crises of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology (Northwestern University 1970), e.g., at 127.
- Carr, David (1970) "Translator's Introduction" xv–xliii, at xxxviii–xlii, to Husserl, The Crises of European Sciences.
- Beyer, Christian (2022), Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), "Edmund Husserl", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2022 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 26 February 2025
- Hugo Ott, Martin Heidegger, Unterwegs zu seiner Biographie. Campus Verlag p.168, Walter Biemel "Erinnerungsfragmente" in Erinnerung an Martin Heidegger Neske 1977 S.22
- Rüdiger Safranski, Martin Heidegger: Between Good and Evil (Cambridge, Mass., & London: Harvard University Press, 1998), pp. 253–8.
- Spiegelberg, Herbert (1971). The Phenomenological Movement. A historical introduction. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 2d ed. ISBN 9024702399. Vol. I. pp. 281–283. "Around this time, Husserl also began to refer to Heidegger and Scheler as his philosophical antipodes." Spiegelberg (1970) at p. 283.
- Husserl, Edmund (1997). Psychological and Transcendental Phenomenology and the Confrontation with Heidegger (1927–1931), translated by T. Sheehan and R. Palmer. Dordrecht: Kluwer. ISBN 0792344812, which contains his "Phänomenologie und Anthropologie" at pp. 485–500.
- "Nur noch ein Gott kann uns retten". Der Spiegel, 31 May 1967.
- Richard Evans, The Coming of the Third Reich (Penguin 2003), p. 421.
- Cf., Peter Koestenbaum, "Introductory Essay" ix–lxxvii, at lxxv–lxxvi, in his edited Edmund Husserl, The Paris Lectures (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 2d ed. 1967). His widow Malvine Husserl was instrumental in this rescue project; she became a convert to Catholicism in 1941.
- Kockelmans, "The Husserl-Archives", at 20–21, in his edited Phenomenology (Doubleday Anchor 1967).
- Philosophy from an Empirical Standpoint: Essays on Carl Stumpf. BRILL. 2 June 2015. p. 159. ISBN 978-90-04-29910-8.
- Simons, Peter, Parts: A Study in Ontology, Oxford University Press
- Chisholm, R. M. (1967). "Intentionality". The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 4: 201.
- Warren, Nicolas de (5 November 2009). Husserl and the Promise of Time: Subjectivity in Transcendental Phenomenology. Cambridge University Press. p. 79. ISBN 978-0-521-87679-7.
- Boer, Theodorus A. de (31 December 1978). The Development of Husserl's Thought. Springer. p. 121. ISBN 978-90-247-2039-2. Retrieved 18 April 2013.
- This assumption led Husserl to an idealistic position (which he originally had tried to overcome or avoid). On Husserl's phenomenological idealism see Hans Köchler, Die Subjekt-Objekt-Dialektik in der transzendentalen Phänomenologie. Das Seinsproblem zwischen Idealismus und Realismus. (Monographien zur philosophischen Forschung, Vol. 112.) Meisenheim a. G.: Anton Hain, 1974.
- Crisis of European Humanity, Pt. II, 1935
- Ralph Keen (24 November 2009). Exile and Restoration in Jewish Thought: An Essay in Interpretation. Continuum. p. 68. ISBN 978-0-8264-5308-2. Retrieved 21 December 2012.
- Edmund Husserl, Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology, tr. W. R. Boyce Gibson (New York: Macmillan, 1962) 96–103, 155–67.
- Husserl, Ideas 194.
- Husserl, Ideas 242–43.
- Husserl, Ideas 105–109; Mark P. Drost, 'The Primacy of Perception in Husserl's Theory of Imagining,' PPR 1 (1990) 569–82. The German begreifen, cognate with English 'grip,' carries the same sense.
- Burgin, Mark (27 October 2016). Theory Of Knowledge: Structures And Processes. World Scientific. p. 468. ISBN 978-981-4522-69-4.
- Hill, Claire Ortiz; Haddock, Guillermo E. Rosado (2000). Husserl Or Frege?: Meaning, Objectivity, and Mathematics. Open Court Publishing. p. 35. ISBN 978-0-8126-9417-8.
- Dahlstrom, D. O. (2004). "Ontology". New Catholic Encyclopedia. Gale.
- Sandkühler, Hans Jörg (2010). "Ontologie". Enzyklopädie Philosophie. Meiner. Archived from the original on 11 March 2021. Retrieved 22 December 2020.
- Gander, Hans-Helmuth (2009). "Ontologie". Husserl Lexikon. Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
- Føllesdal, Dagfinn (2006). "Husserl's Reductions and the Role They Play in His Phenomenology". A Companion to Phenomenology and Existentialism. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 105–114. doi:10.1002/9780470996508.ch8. ISBN 978-0-470-99650-8.
- Drummond, John J. (2009). "Formal ontology". Historical Dictionary of Husserl's Philosophy. Scarecrow.
- Poli, Roberto (1993). "Husserl's Conception of Formal Ontology". History and Philosophy of Logic. 14: 1–14. doi:10.1080/01445349308837207.
- Moran, Dermot; Cohen, Joseph (2012). "Regional ontology". The Husserl Dictionary. Continuum.
- Drummond, John J. (2009). "Eidetic variation". Historical Dictionary of Husserl's Philosophy. Scarecrow.
- Spear, Andrew D. "Husserl, Edmund: Intentionality and Intentional Content". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 22 December 2020.
- Klein, Jacob (22 April 2013). Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra. Courier Corporation. ISBN 978-0-486-31981-0.
- Alfred Schramm, Meinongian Issues in Contemporary Italian Philosophy, Walter de Gruyter, 2009, p. 28.
- Consider Jitendra Nath Mohanty, 1995, "The Development of Husserl's Thought" in Barry Smith and David Woodruff Smith, eds., The Cambridge Companion to Husserl, Cambridge University Press. For further commentaries on the review, see Willard, Dallas, 1984. Logic and the Objectivity of Knowledge. Athens OH: Ohio University Press, p. 63; J. Philip Miller, 1982. "Numbers in Presence and Absence, Phaenomenologica 90 (Den Haag: Nijhoff): p. 19 ff.; and Jitendra Nath Mohanty, 1984, "Husserl, Frege and the Overcoming of Psychologism", in Cho, Kay Kyung, ed., Philosophy and Science in Phenomenological Perspective, Phaenomenologica 95 (Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster: Nijhoff), p. 145.
- Hill, Claire Ortiz; Haddock, Guillermo E. Rosado (2000). Husserl Or Frege?: Meaning, Objectivity, and Mathematics. Open Court Publishing. pp. 253–262. ISBN 978-0-8126-9417-8.
- Husserl-Chronik, pp. 25–26
- Golomb, Jacob (1976). "Psychology from the Phenomenological Standpoint of Husserl". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 36 (4): 451–471. doi:10.2307/2106865. ISSN 0031-8205. JSTOR 2106865.
- See the quotes in Carlo Ierna, "Husserl's Critique of Double Judgments", in: Filip Mattens, editor, Meaning and Language: Phenomenological Perspectives, Phaenomenologica 187 (Dordrecht/Boston/London: Springer, 2008, pp. 50 f.
- Edmund Husserl, Logical Investigations, volume 1, edited by Dermot Moran, trans. by J.N. Findlay (New York: Routledge, 2001), p. 112.
- Gutland, Christopher (15 April 2019). Denk-Erfahrung: Eine phänomenologisch orientierte Untersuchung der Erfahrbarkeit des Denkens und der Gedanken (in German). Verlag Karl Alber. p. 344. ISBN 978-3-495-81759-9.
- Drummond, J. J. (6 December 2012). Husserlian Intentionality and Non-Foundational Realism: Noema and Object. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 261. ISBN 978-94-009-1974-7.
- Carr, David (1970), "Translator's Introduction", xv–xlii, at xxv, to Edmund Husserl, The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology. Northwestern University Press.
- Kockelmans, "Introduction [Martin Heidegger]" 267–276, 273, in Kockelmans, editor, Phenomenology (1967).
- Beyer, Christian (23 August 2017). "Edmund Husserl". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Heidegger was at Marburg 1923–1925.
- See above subsection "Heidegger and the Nazi era".
- The multivalent, including the "horrifying", aspects of Heidegger in a parallel context are recounted in Peter Eli Gordon, Rosensweig and Heidegger: Between Judaism and German Philosophy (University of California 2003) at 13–14 (Heidegger and Rosensweig's early "kinship" with him). "In 1929, however, one could still read Heidegger's philosophy without being drawn into a controversy concerning its relationship to National Socialism, antisemitism, and the like. The German philosophical world as a whole still cloaked itself in a mantle of relative innocence." Gordon (2003) at 303–304. "Rosensweig's work represents the culmination of what is often called the German Jewish Tradition." Gordon, "Preface" (2003) at xix.
- Edith Stein, Reinach as a Philosophical Personality [Selection from her memoirs] xxvii–xxix, at xxvii, in Aletheia, III (1985).
- Adolf Reinach, "Die apriorischen Grundlagen des bürgerlichen Rechtes" in Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, I: 685–847 (1913), translated as "The A Priori Foundation of Civil Law" in Aletheia, III: 1–142 (1983).
- Edmund Husserl, Reinach as a Philosophical Personality [Obituary notice] xi–xiv, at xi, in Aletheia, III (1985).
- Waltraud Herbstrith, Edith Stein: A Biography (New York: Harper and Row, 1985 [1971]), pp. 13–14, 24; 42–44.
- John Raphael Staude, Max Scheler (New York: Free Press 1967) at 19–20, 27–28.
- Spiegelberg, Herbert (1971). The Phenomenological Movement. pp. 258–259; 371 (Scheler), 379–384 (use of method).
- Unsigned "Preface" at vii–x, to Emmanuel Levinas. Basic philosophical writings (Indiana University 1996), edited by Adriaan Peperzak, Simon Critchley, and Robert Bernasconi.
- George Walsh, "Introduction", Alfred Schütz, The Phenomenology of the Social World (Illinois 1997) p. xviii
- Sartre, The Transcendent of the Ego. An Existentialist Theory of Consciousness [1937] (New York: Noonday 1957).
- See, for example, the influence of Husserl on Merleau-Ponty's conception of l'espace as expounded in: Nader El-Bizri, "A Phenomenological Account of the Ontological Problem of Space", Existentia Meletai-Sophias, 12 (2002), pp.345–364
- Lectures, Summer Semester, 1925
- Remy C. Kwant, "Merleau-Ponty's Criticism of Husserl's Eidetic Reduction" in Joseph J. Kochelmans, Phenomenology. The Philosophy of Edmund Husserl and its Interpretation (Garden City NY: Doubleday Anchor 1967) at 393–408, 394–395, 404–405.
- Spiegelberg, Herbert and Schuhmann, Karl (1982). The Phenomenological Movement. Springer. pp. 438–439, 448–449.
- Caponigri, A. Robert (1971). A History of Western Philosophy. University of Notre Dame. Vol. V, pp. 284–285.
- Colin Wilson (1966). Introduction to the New Existentialism. Ashgate Publishing. p. 54. ISBN 978-0-7045-0415-8.
- Smith, D. W., and Thomasson, Amie L. (eds.), 2005, Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, p. 8 n. 18.
- Wojtyla, Karol (2002), The Acting Person: A Contribution to Phenomenological Anthropology, Springer, ISBN 90-277-0985-8
- Cf., Paul Ricœur, Husserl. An analysis of his phenomenology (Northwestern University 1967), collected essays, translated.
- Ricœur, Freud and Philosophy: An essay in interpretation ([1965]; Yale University 1970).
- Cf. Smith, Barry (1989), "On the Origins of Analytic Philosophy" (PDF), Grazer Philosophische Studien, vol. 34, pp. 153–173
- Spiegelberg, Herbert and Schuhmann, Karl (1982). The Phenomenological Movement. Springer. pp. 658–659.
- Sellars, Wilfrid (1975), "Autobiographical Reflections", in Castañeda, Hector-Neri (ed.), Action, Knowledge, and Reality: Critical Studies in Honor of Wilfrid Sellars, Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill
- Scruton, Roger (1994). Sexual Desire: A Philosophical Investigation. London: Phoenix. pp. 3–4. ISBN 1-85799-100-1.
- See for instance: Nader El-Bizri, The Phenomenological Quest Between Avicenna and Heidegger (Binghamton, N.Y.: Global Publications SUNY at Binghamton, 2000); and also refer to: Nader El-Bizri, "Avicenna's De Anima between Aristotle and Husserl", in The Passions of the Soul in the Metamorphosis of Becoming, ed. Anna-Teresa Tymieniecka (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2003), pp. 67–89
- "Islamic Philosophy and Occidental Phenomenology in Dialogue". Springer. Retrieved 26 February 2025.
Further reading
- Adorno, Theodor W., 2013. Against Epistemology. Cambridge: Polity Press. ISBN 978-0745665382
- Bernet, Rudolf, et al., 1993. Introduction to Husserlian Phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. ISBN 0-8101-1030-X
- Derrida, Jacques, 1954 (French), 2003 (English). The Problem of Genesis in Husserl's Philosophy. Chicago & London: University of Chicago Press.
- --------, 1962 (French), 1976 (English). Introduction to Husserl's The Origin of Geometry. Includes Derrida's translation of Appendix III of Husserl's 1936 The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology.
- --------, 1967 (French), 1973 (English). Speech and Phenomena (La Voix et le Phénomène), and other Essays on Husserl's Theory of Signs. ISBN 0-8101-0397-4
- Fink, Eugen 1995, Sixth Cartesian meditation. The Idea of a Transcendental Theory of Method with textual notations by Edmund Husserl. Translated with an introduction by Ronald Bruzina, Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
- Hill, C. O., 1991. Word and Object in Husserl, Frege, and Russell: The Roots of Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Ohio Univ. Press.
- Hopkins, Burt C., (2011). The Philosophy of Husserl. Durham: Acumen.
- Levinas, Emmanuel, 1963 (French), 1973 (English). The Theory of Intuition in Husserl's Phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
- Köchler, Hans, 1982. Edmund Husserl's Theory of Meaning. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
- --------, 1982. Husserl and Frege. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
- Moran, D. and Cohen, J., 2012, The Husserl Dictionary. London, Continuum Press.
- Natanson, Maurice, 1973. Edmund Husserl: Philosopher of Infinite Tasks. Evanston: Northwestern University Press. ISBN 0-8101-0425-3
- Ortiz Hill, Claire; da Silva, Jairo Jose, eds. (1997). The Road Not Taken: On Husserl's Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics. College Publications.
- Ricœur, Paul, 1967. Husserl: An Analysis of His Phenomenology. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
- Rollinger, R. D., 2008. Austrian Phenomenology: Brentano, Husserl, Meinong, and Others on Mind and Language. Frankfurt am Main: Ontos-Verlag. ISBN 978-3-86838-005-7
- Sokolowski, Robert. Introduction to Phenomenology. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999. ISBN 978-0-521-66792-0
- Smith, B.; Smith, D. W., eds. (1995), The Cambridge Companion to Husserl, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-43616-8
- Smith, David Woodruff, 2007. Husserl. London: Routledge.
- Zahavi, Dan, 2003. Husserl's Phenomenology. Stanford: Stanford University Press. ISBN 0-8047-4546-3
External links
Husserl archives
- Husserl-Archives Leuven, the main Husserl-Archive in Leuven, International Centre for Phenomenological Research.
- Husserliana: Edmund Husserl Gesammelte Werke, the ongoing critical edition of Husserl's works.
- Husserliana: Materialien, edition for lectures and shorter works.
- Edmund Husserl Collected Works, English translation of Husserl's works.
- Husserl-Archives at the University of Cologne.
- Husserl-Archives Freiburg.
- Archives Husserl de Paris, at the École normale supérieure, Paris.
- Works by or about Edmund Husserl at the Internet Archive
Other links
- Beyer, Christian. "Edmund Husserl". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Smith, David Woodruff. "Phenomenology". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Papers on Edmund Husserl by Barry Smith
- English translation of "Vienna Lecture" (1935): "Philosophy and the Crisis of European Humanity"
- The Husserl Page by Bob Sandmeyer. Includes a number of online texts in German and English.
- Husserl.net, open content project.
- "Edmund Husserl: Formal Ontology and Transcendental Logic." Resource guide on Husserl's logic and formal ontology, with annotated bibliography.
- The Husserl Circle.
- Cartesian Meditations in Internet Archive
- Ideas, Part I in Internet Archive
- Edmund Husserl on the Open Commons of Phenomenology. Complete bibliography and links to all German texts, including Husserliana vols. I–XXVIII
Edmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl ˈ h ʊ s ɜːr l HUUSS url US also ˈ h ʊ s er el HUUSS er el German ˈɛtmʊnt ˈhʊsɐl 8 April 1859 27 April 1938 was an Austrian German philosopher and mathematician who established the school of phenomenology Edmund HusserlHusserl c 1910sBornEdmund Gustav Albrecht Husserl 8 April 1859 Prossnitz Moravia Austrian EmpireDied27 April 1938 1938 04 27 aged 79 Freiburg GermanyAcademic backgroundEducationLeipzig UniversityUniversity of BerlinUniversity of Vienna PhD 1883 University of Halle Dr phil hab 1887 Signature In his early work he elaborated critiques of historicism and of psychologism in logic based on analyses of intentionality In his mature work he sought to develop a systematic foundational science based on the so called phenomenological reduction Arguing that transcendental consciousness sets the limits of all possible knowledge Husserl redefined phenomenology as a transcendental idealist philosophy Husserl s thought profoundly influenced 20th century philosophy and he remains a notable figure in contemporary philosophy and beyond Husserl studied mathematics taught by Karl Weierstrass and Leo Konigsberger and philosophy taught by Franz Brentano and Carl Stumpf He taught philosophy as a Privatdozent at Halle from 1887 then as professor first at Gottingen from 1901 then at Freiburg from 1916 until he retired in 1928 after which he remained highly productive In 1933 under racial laws of the Nazi Party Husserl was banned from using the library of the University of Freiburg due to his Jewish family background and months later resigned from the Deutsche Akademie Following an illness he died in Freiburg in 1938 Life and careerYouth and education Husserl was born in 1859 in Prossnitz in the Margraviate of Moravia in the Austrian Empire today Prostejov in the Czech Republic He was born into a Jewish family the second of four children His father was a milliner His childhood was spent in Prostejov where he attended the secular primary school Then Husserl traveled to Vienna to study at the Realgymnasium there followed next by the Staatsgymnasium in Olmutz At the University of Leipzig from 1876 to 1878 Husserl studied mathematics physics and astronomy At Leipzig he was inspired by philosophy lectures given by Wilhelm Wundt one of the founders of modern psychology Then he moved to the Frederick William University of Berlin the present day Humboldt University of Berlin in 1878 where he continued his study of mathematics under Leopold Kronecker and Karl Weierstrass In Berlin he found a mentor in Tomas Garrigue Masaryk then a former philosophy student of Franz Brentano and later the first president of Czechoslovakia There Husserl also attended Friedrich Paulsen s philosophy lectures In 1881 he left for the University of Vienna to complete his mathematics studies under the supervision of Leo Konigsberger a former student of Weierstrass At Vienna in 1883 he obtained his PhD with the work Beitrage zur Variationsrechnung Contributions to the Calculus of variations Evidently as a result of his becoming familiar with the New Testament during his twenties Husserl asked to be baptized into the Lutheran Church in 1886 Husserl s father Adolf had died in 1884 Herbert Spiegelberg writes While outward religious practice never entered his life any more than it did that of most academic scholars of the time his mind remained open for the religious phenomenon as for any other genuine experience At times Husserl saw his goal as one of moral renewal Although a steadfast proponent of a radical and rational autonomy in all things Husserl could also speak about his vocation and even about his mission under God s will to find new ways for philosophy and science observes Spiegelberg Following his PhD in mathematics Husserl returned to Berlin to work as the assistant to Karl Weierstrass Yet already Husserl had felt the desire to pursue philosophy Then professor Weierstrass became very ill Husserl became free to return to Vienna where after serving a short military duty he devoted his attention to philosophy In 1884 at the University of Vienna he attended the lectures of Franz Brentano on philosophy and philosophical psychology Brentano introduced him to the writings of Bernard Bolzano Hermann Lotze J Stuart Mill and David Hume Husserl was so impressed by Brentano that he decided to dedicate his life to philosophy indeed Franz Brentano is often credited as being his most important influence e g with regard to intentionality Following academic advice two years later in 1886 Husserl followed Carl Stumpf a former student of Brentano to the University of Halle seeking to obtain his habilitation which would qualify him to teach at the university level There under Stumpf s supervision he wrote Uber den Begriff der Zahl On the Concept of Number in 1887 which would serve later as the basis for his first important work Philosophie der Arithmetik 1891 In 1887 Husserl married Malvine Steinschneider a union that would last over fifty years In 1892 their daughter Elizabeth was born in 1893 their son Gerhart and in 1894 their son Wolfgang Elizabeth would marry in 1922 and Gerhart in 1923 Wolfgang however became a casualty of the First World War Gerhart would become a philosopher of law contributing to the subject of comparative law teaching in the United States and after the war in Austria Professor of philosophy Edmund Husserl c 1900 Following his marriage Husserl began his long teaching career in philosophy He started in 1887 as a Privatdozent at the University of Halle In 1891 he published his Philosophie der Arithmetik Psychologische und logische Untersuchungen which drawing on his prior studies in mathematics and philosophy proposed a psychological context as the basis of mathematics It drew the adverse notice of Gottlob Frege who criticized its psychologism In 1901 Husserl with his family moved to the University of Gottingen where he taught as extraordinarius professor Just prior to this a major work of his Logische Untersuchungen Halle 1900 1901 was published Volume One contains seasoned reflections on pure logic in which he carefully refutes psychologism This work was well received and became the subject of a seminar given by Wilhelm Dilthey Husserl in 1905 traveled to Berlin to visit Dilthey Two years later in Italy he paid a visit to Franz Brentano his inspiring old teacher and to the mathematician Constantin Caratheodory Kant and Descartes were also now influencing his thought In 1910 he became joint editor of the journal Logos During this period Husserl had delivered lectures on internal time consciousness which several decades later his former students Edith Stein and Martin Heidegger edited for publication In 1912 at Freiburg the journal Jahrbuch fur Philosophie und Phanomenologische Forschung Yearbook for Philosophy and Phenomenological Research was founded by Husserl and his school and which published articles of their phenomenological movement from 1913 to 1930 His important work Ideen was published in its first issue Vol 1 Issue 1 1913 Before beginning Ideen Husserl s thought had reached the stage where each subject is presented to itself and to each all others are presentiated Vergegenwartigung not as parts of nature but as pure consciousness Ideen advanced his transition to a transcendental interpretation of phenomenology a view later criticized by among others Jean Paul Sartre In Ideen Paul Ricœur sees the development of Husserl s thought as leading from the psychological cogito to the transcendental cogito As phenomenology further evolves it leads when viewed from another vantage point in Husserl s labyrinth to transcendental subjectivity Also in Ideen Husserl explicitly elaborates the phenomenological and eidetic reductions Ivan Ilyin and Karl Jaspers visited Husserl at Gottingen In October 1914 both his sons were sent to fight on the Western Front of World War I and the following year one of them Wolfgang Husserl was badly injured On 8 March 1916 on the battlefield of Verdun Wolfgang was killed in action The next year his other son Gerhart Husserl was wounded in the war but survived His own mother Julia died In November 1917 one of his outstanding students and later a noted philosophy professor in his own right Adolf Reinach was killed in the war while serving in Flanders Husserl had transferred in 1916 to the University of Freiburg in Freiburg im Breisgau where he continued bringing his work in philosophy to fruition now as a full professor Edith Stein served as his personal assistant during his first few years in Freiburg followed later by Martin Heidegger from 1920 to 1923 The mathematician Hermann Weyl began corresponding with him in 1918 Husserl gave four lectures on Phenomenological method at University College London in 1922 The University of Berlin in 1923 called on him to relocate there but he declined the offer In 1926 Heidegger dedicated his book Sein und Zeit Being and Time to him in grateful respect and friendship Husserl remained in his professorship at Freiburg until he requested retirement teaching his last class on 25 July 1928 A Festschrift to celebrate his seventieth birthday was presented to him on 8 April 1929 Despite retirement Husserl gave several notable lectures The first at Paris in 1929 led to Meditations cartesiennes Paris 1931 Husserl here reviews the phenomenological epoche or phenomenological reduction presented earlier in his pivotal Ideen 1913 in terms of a further reduction of experience to what he calls a sphere of ownness From within this sphere which Husserl enacts to show the impossibility of solipsism the transcendental ego finds itself always already paired with the lived body of another ego another monad This a priori interconnection of bodies given in perception is what founds the interconnection of consciousnesses known as transcendental intersubjectivity which Husserl would go on to describe at length in volumes of unpublished writings There has been a debate over whether or not Husserl s description of ownness and its movement into intersubjectivity is sufficient to reject the charge of solipsism to which Descartes for example was subject One argument against Husserl s description works this way instead of infinity and the Deity being the ego s gateway to the Other as in Descartes Husserl s ego in the Cartesian Meditations itself becomes transcendent It remains however alone unconnected Only the ego s grasp by analogy of the Other e g by conjectural reciprocity allows the possibility for an objective intersubjectivity and hence for community In 1933 the racial laws of the new National Socialist German Workers Party were enacted On 6 April Husserl was banned from using the library at the University of Freiburg or any other academic library the following week after a public outcry he was reinstated Yet his colleague Heidegger was elected Rector of the university on 21 22 April and joined the Nazi Party By contrast in July Husserl resigned from the Deutsche Akademie The Kiepenheuer Institute for Solar Physics in Freiburg Husserl s home 1937 1938 Later Husserl lectured at Prague in 1935 and Vienna in 1936 which resulted in a very differently styled work that while innovative is no less problematic Die Krisis Belgrade 1936 Husserl describes here the cultural crisis gripping Europe then approaches a philosophy of history discussing Galileo Descartes several British philosophers and Kant The apolitical Husserl before had specifically avoided such historical discussions pointedly preferring to go directly to an investigation of consciousness Merleau Ponty and others question whether Husserl here does not undercut his own position in that Husserl had attacked in principle historicism while specifically designing his phenomenology to be rigorous enough to transcend the limits of history On the contrary Husserl may be indicating here that historical traditions are merely features given to the pure ego s intuition like any other A longer section follows on the lifeworld Lebenswelt one not observed by the objective logic of science but a world seen through subjective experience Yet a problem arises similar to that dealing with history above a chicken and egg problem Does the lifeworld contextualize and thus compromise the gaze of the pure ego or does the phenomenological method nonetheless raise the ego up transcendent These last writings presented the fruits of his professional life Since his university retirement Husserl had worked at a tremendous pace producing several major works After suffering a fall in the autumn of 1937 the philosopher became ill with pleurisy Edmund Husserl died in Freiburg on 27 April 1938 having just turned 79 His wife Malvine survived him Eugen Fink his research assistant delivered his eulogy Gerhard Ritter was the only Freiburg faculty member to attend the funeral as an anti Nazi protest Heidegger and the Nazi era Husserl was rumoured to have been denied the use of the library at Freiburg as a result of the anti Jewish legislation of April 1933 Relatedly among other disabilities Husserl was unable to publish his works in Nazi Germany see above footnote to Die Krisis 1936 It was also rumoured that his former pupil Martin Heidegger informed Husserl that he was discharged but it was actually the previous rector Apparently Husserl and Heidegger had moved apart during the 1920s which became clearer after 1928 when Husserl retired and Heidegger succeeded to his university chair In the summer of 1929 Husserl had studied carefully selected writings of Heidegger coming to the conclusion that on several of their key positions they differed e g Heidegger substituted Dasein Being there for the pure ego thus transforming phenomenology into an anthropology a type of psychologism strongly disfavored by Husserl Such observations of Heidegger along with a critique of Max Scheler were put into a lecture Husserl gave to various Kant Societies in Frankfurt Berlin and Halle during 1931 entitled Phanomenologie und Anthropologie In the war time 1941 edition of Heidegger s primary work Being and Time Sein und Zeit first published in 1927 the original dedication to Husserl was removed This was not due to a negation of the relationship between the two philosophers however but rather was the result of a suggested censorship by Heidegger s publisher who feared that the book might otherwise be banned by the Nazi regime The dedication can still be found in a footnote on page 38 thanking Husserl for his guidance and generosity Husserl had died three years earlier In post war editions of Sein und Zeit the dedication to Husserl is restored The complex troubled and sundered philosophical relationship between Husserl and Heidegger has been widely discussed On 4 May 1933 Professor Edmund Husserl addressed the recent regime change in Germany and its consequences The future alone will judge which was the true Germany in 1933 and who were the true Germans those who subscribe to the more or less materialistic mythical racial prejudices of the day or those Germans pure in heart and mind heirs to the great Germans of the past whose tradition they revere and perpetuate After his death Husserl s manuscripts amounting to approximately 40 000 pages of Gabelsberger stenography and his complete research library were in 1939 smuggled to the Catholic University of Leuven in Belgium by the Franciscan priest Herman Van Breda There they were deposited at Leuven to form the Husserl Archives of the Higher Institute of Philosophy Much of the material in his research manuscripts has since been published in the Husserliana critical edition series Development of his thoughtSeveral early themes In his first works Husserl combined mathematics psychology and philosophy with the goal of providing a sound foundation for mathematics He analyzed the psychological process needed to obtain the concept of number and then built up a theory on this analysis He used methods and concepts taken from his teachers From Weierstrass he derived the idea of generating the concept of number by counting a certain collection of objects From Brentano and Stumpf he took the distinction between proper and improper presenting 159 In an example Husserl explained this in the following way if someone is standing in front of a house they have a proper direct presentation of that house but if they are looking for it and ask for directions then these directions e g the house on the corner of this and that street are an indirect improper presentation In other words the person can have a proper presentation of an object if it is actually present and an improper or symbolic as Husserl also calls it one if they only can indicate that object through signs symbols etc Husserl s Logical Investigations 1900 1901 is considered the starting point for the formal theory of wholes and their parts known as mereology Another important element that Husserl took over from Brentano was intentionality the notion that the main characteristic of consciousness is that it is always intentional While often simplistically summarised as aboutness or the relationship between mental acts and the external world Brentano defined it as the main characteristic of mental phenomena by which they could be distinguished from physical phenomena Every mental phenomenon every psychological act has a content is directed at an object the intentional object Every belief desire etc has an object that it is about the believed the wanted Brentano used the expression intentional inexistence to indicate the status of the objects of thought in the mind The property of being intentional of having an intentional object was the key feature to distinguish mental phenomena and physical phenomena because physical phenomena lack intentionality altogether The elaboration of phenomenology Some years after the 1900 1901 publication of his main work the Logische Untersuchungen Logical Investigations Husserl made some key conceptual elaborations which led him to assert that to study the structure of consciousness one would have to distinguish between the act of consciousness and the phenomena at which it is directed the objects as intended Knowledge of essences would only be possible by bracketing all assumptions about the existence of an external world This procedure he called epoche These new concepts prompted the publication of the Ideen Ideas in 1913 in which they were at first incorporated and a plan for a second edition of the Logische Untersuchungen From the Ideen onward Husserl concentrated on the ideal essential structures of consciousness The metaphysical problem of establishing the reality of what people perceive as distinct from the perceiving subject was of little interest to Husserl in spite of his being a transcendental idealist Husserl proposed that the world of objects and of ways in which people direct themselves toward and perceive those objects is normally conceived of in what he called the natural attitude which is characterized by a belief that objects exist distinct from the perceiving subject and exhibit properties that people see as emanating from them this attitude is also called physicalist objectivism Husserl proposed a radical new phenomenological way of looking at objects by examining how people in their many ways of being intentionally directed toward them actually constitute them to be distinguished from materially creating objects or objects merely being figments of the imagination in the Phenomenological standpoint the object ceases to be something simply external and ceases to be seen as providing indicators about what it is and becomes a grouping of perceptual and functional aspects that imply one another under the idea of a particular object or type The notion of objects as real is not expelled by phenomenology but bracketed as a way in which people regard objects instead of a feature that inheres in an object s essence founded in the relation between the object and the perceiver To better understand the world of appearances and objects phenomenology attempts to identify the invariant features of how objects are perceived and pushes attributions of reality into their role as an attribution about the things people perceive or an assumption underlying how people perceive objects The major dividing line in Husserl s thought is the turn to transcendental idealism In a later period Husserl began to wrestle with the complicated issues of intersubjectivity specifically how communication about an object can be assumed to refer to the same ideal entity Cartesian Meditations Meditation V Husserl tries new methods of bringing his readers to understand the importance of phenomenology to scientific inquiry and specifically to psychology and what it means to bracket the natural attitude The Crisis of the European Sciences is Husserl s unfinished work that deals most directly with these issues In it Husserl for the first time attempts a historical overview of the development of Western philosophy and science emphasizing the challenges presented by their increasingly one sidedly empirical and naturalistic orientation Husserl declares that mental and spiritual reality possess their own reality independent of any physical basis and that a science of the mind Geisteswissenschaft must be established on as scientific a foundation as the natural sciences have managed It is my conviction that intentional phenomenology has for the first time made spirit as spirit the field of systematic scientific experience thus effecting a total transformation of the task of knowledge Husserl s thoughtHusserl s thought is revolutionary in several ways most notably in the distinction between natural and phenomenological modes of understanding In the former sense perception in correspondence with the material realm constitutes the known reality and understanding is premised on the accuracy of the perception and the objective knowability of what is called the real world Phenomenological understanding strives to be rigorously presuppositionless by means of what Husserl calls phenomenological reduction This reduction is not conditioned but rather transcendental in Husserl s terms pure consciousness of absolute Being In Husserl s work consciousness of any given thing calls for discerning its meaning as an intentional object Such an object does not simply strike the senses to be interpreted or misinterpreted by mental reason it has already been selected and grasped grasping being an etymological connotation of percipere the root of perceive Meaning and object From Logical Investigations 1900 1901 to Experience and Judgment published in 1939 Husserl expressed clearly the difference between meaning and object He identified several different kinds of names For example there are names that have the role of properties that uniquely identify an object Each of these names expresses a meaning and designates the same object Examples of this are the victor in Jena and the loser in Waterloo or the equilateral triangle and the equiangular triangle in both cases both names express different meanings but designate the same object There are names which have no meaning but have the role of designating an object Aristotle Socrates and so on Finally there are names which designate a variety of objects These are called universal names their meaning is a concept and refers to a series of objects the extension of the concept The way people know sensible objects is called sensible intuition Husserl also identifies a series of formal words which are necessary to form sentences and have no sensible correlates Examples of formal words are a the more than over under two group and so on Every sentence must contain formal words to designate what Husserl calls formal categories There are two kinds of categories meaning categories and formal ontological categories Meaning categories relate judgments they include forms of conjunction disjunction forms of plural among others Formal ontological categories relate objects and include notions such as set cardinal number ordinal number part and whole relation and so on The way people know these categories is through a faculty of understanding called categorial intuition Through sensible intuition consciousness constitutes what Husserl calls a situation of affairs Sachlage It is a passive constitution where objects themselves are presented To this situation of affairs through categorial intuition people are able to constitute a state of affairs Sachverhalt One situation of affairs through objective acts of consciousness acts of constituting categorially can serve as the basis for constituting multiple states of affairs For example suppose a and b are two sensible objects in a certain situation of affairs It can be used as the basis to say a lt b and b gt a two judgments which designate the same state of affairs For Husserl a sentence has a proposition or judgment as its meaning and refers to a state of affairs which has a situation of affairs as a reference base 35 Formal and regional ontology Husserl sees ontology as a science of essences Sciences of essences are contrasted with factual sciences the former are knowable a priori and provide the foundation for the later which are knowable a posteriori Ontology as a science of essences is not interested in actual facts but in the essences themselves whether they have instances or not Husserl distinguishes between formal ontology which investigates the essence of objectivity in general and regional ontologies which study regional essences that are shared by all entities belonging to the region Regions correspond to the highest genera of concrete entities material nature personal consciousness and interpersonal spirit Husserl s method for studying ontology and sciences of essence in general is called eidetic variation It involves imagining an object of the kind under investigation and varying its features The changed feature is inessential to this kind if the object can survive its change otherwise it belongs to the kind s essence For example a triangle remains a triangle if one of its sides is extended but it ceases to be a triangle if a fourth side is added Regional ontology involves applying this method to the essences corresponding to the highest genera Philosophy of logic and mathematics Husserl believed that truth in itself has as ontological correlate being in itself just as meaning categories have formal ontological categories as correlates Logic is a formal theory of judgment that studies the formal a priori relations among judgments using meaning categories Mathematics on the other hand is formal ontology it studies all the possible forms of being of objects Hence for both logic and mathematics the different formal categories are the objects of study not the sensible objects themselves The problem with the psychological approach to mathematics and logic is that it fails to account for the fact that this approach is about formal categories and not simply about abstractions from sensibility alone The reason why sensible objects are not dealt with in mathematics is because of another faculty of understanding called categorial abstraction Through this faculty people are able to get rid of sensible components of judgments and just focus on formal categories themselves Thanks to eidetic reduction or essential intuition people are able to grasp the possibility impossibility necessity and contingency among concepts and among formal categories Categorial intuition along with categorial abstraction and eidetic reduction are the basis for logical and mathematical knowledge Husserl criticized the logicians of his day for not focusing on the relation between subjective processes that offer objective knowledge of pure logic All subjective activities of consciousness need an ideal correlate and objective logic constituted noematically as it is constituted by consciousness needs a noetic correlate the subjective activities of consciousness Husserl stated that logic has three strata each further away from consciousness and psychology than those that precede it The first stratum is what Husserl called a morphology of meanings concerning a priori ways to relate judgments to make them meaningful In this stratum people elaborate a pure grammar or a logical syntax and he would call its rules laws to prevent non sense which would be similar to what logic calls today formation rules Mathematics as logic s ontological correlate also has a similar stratum a morphology of formal ontological categories The second stratum would be called by Husserl logic of consequence or the logic of non contradiction which explores all possible forms of true judgments He includes here syllogistic classic logic propositional logic and that of predicates This is a semantic stratum and the rules of this stratum would be the laws to avoid counter sense or laws to prevent contradiction They are very similar to today s logic transformation rules Mathematics also has a similar stratum which is based among others on pure theory of pluralities and a pure theory of numbers They provide a science of the conditions of possibility of any theory whatsoever Husserl also talked about what he called logic of truth which consists of the formal laws of possible truth and its modalities and precedes the third logical third stratum The third stratum is metalogical what he called a theory of all possible forms of theories It explores all possible theories in an a priori fashion rather than the possibility of theory in general Theories of possible relations between pure forms of theories could be established these logical relations could in turn be investigated using deduction The logician is free to see the extension of this deductive theoretical sphere of pure logic The ontological correlate to the third stratum is the theory of manifolds In formal ontology it is a free investigation where a mathematician can assign several meanings to several symbols and all their possible valid deductions in a general and indeterminate manner It is properly speaking the most universal mathematics of all Through the posit of certain indeterminate objects formal ontological categories as well as any combination of mathematical axioms mathematicians can explore the apodeictic connections between them as long as consistency is preserved According to Husserl this view of logic and mathematics accounted for the objectivity of a series of mathematical developments of his time such as n dimensional manifolds both Euclidean and non Euclidean Hermann Grassmann s theory of extensions William Rowan Hamilton s Hamiltonians Sophus Lie s theory of transformation groups and Cantor s set theory Jacob Klein was one student of Husserl who pursued this line of inquiry seeking to desedimentize mathematics and the mathematical sciences Husserl and psychologismPhilosophy of arithmetic and Frege After obtaining his PhD in mathematics Husserl began analyzing the foundations of mathematics from a psychological point of view In his habilitation thesis On the Concept of Number 1886 and in his Philosophy of Arithmetic 1891 Husserl sought by employing Brentano s descriptive psychology to define the natural numbers in a way that advanced the methods and techniques of Karl Weierstrass Richard Dedekind Georg Cantor Gottlob Frege and other contemporary mathematicians Later in the first volume of his Logical Investigations the Prolegomena of Pure Logic Husserl while attacking the psychologistic point of view in logic and mathematics also appears to reject much of his early work although the forms of psychologism analysed and refuted in the Prolegomena did not apply directly to his Philosophy of Arithmetic Some scholars question whether Frege s negative review of the Philosophy of Arithmetic helped turn Husserl towards modern Platonism but he had already discovered the work of Bernard Bolzano independently around 1890 91 In his Logical Investigations Husserl explicitly mentioned Bolzano G W Leibniz and Hermann Lotze as inspirations for his newer position Husserl s review of Ernst Schroder published before Frege s landmark 1892 article clearly distinguishes sense from reference thus Husserl s notions of noema and object also arose independently Likewise in his criticism of Frege in the Philosophy of Arithmetic Husserl remarks on the distinction between the content and the extension of a concept Moreover the distinction between the subjective mental act namely the content of a concept and the external object was developed independently by Brentano and his school and may have surfaced as early as Brentano s 1870s lectures on logic Scholars such as J N Mohanty Claire Ortiz Hill and among others have argued that Husserl s so called change from psychologism to Platonism came about independently of Frege s review 253 262 For example the review falsely accuses Husserl of subjectivizing everything so that no objectivity is possible and falsely attributes to him a notion of abstraction whereby objects disappear until all that remains are numbers as mere ghosts citation needed Contrary to what Frege states in Husserl s Philosophy of Arithmetic there are already two different kinds of representations subjective and objective Moreover objectivity is clearly defined in that work Frege s attack seems to be directed at certain foundational doctrines then current in Weierstrass s Berlin School of which Husserl and Cantor cannot be said to be orthodox representatives Furthermore various sources indicate that Husserl changed his mind about psychologism as early as 1890 a year before he published the Philosophy of Arithmetic Husserl stated that by the time he published that book he had already changed his mind that he had doubts about psychologism from the very outset He attributed this change of mind to his reading of Leibniz Bolzano Lotze and David Hume Husserl makes no mention of Frege as a decisive factor in this change In his Logical Investigations Husserl mentions Frege only twice once in a footnote to point out that he had retracted three pages of his criticism of Frege s The Foundations of Arithmetic and again to question Frege s use of the word Bedeutung to designate reference rather than meaning sense In a letter dated 24 May 1891 Frege thanked Husserl for sending him a copy of the Philosophy of Arithmetic and Husserl s review of Ernst Schroder s Vorlesungen uber die Algebra der Logik In the same letter Frege used the review of Schroder s book to analyze Husserl s notion of the sense of reference of concept words Hence Frege recognized as early as 1891 that Husserl distinguished between sense and reference Consequently Frege and Husserl independently elaborated a theory of sense and reference before 1891 Commentators argue that Husserl s notion of noema has nothing to do with Frege s notion of sense because noemata are necessarily fused with noeses which are the conscious activities of consciousness Noemata have three different levels The substratum which is never presented to the consciousness and is the support of all the properties of the object The noematic senses which are the different ways the objects are presented to us The modalities of being possible doubtful existent non existent absurd and so on Consequently in intentional activities even non existent objects can be constituted and form part of the whole noema Frege however did not conceive of objects as forming parts of senses If a proper name denotes a non existent object it does not have a reference hence concepts with no objects have no truth value in arguments Moreover Husserl did not maintain that predicates of sentences designate concepts According to Frege the reference of a sentence is a truth value for Husserl it is a state of affairs Frege s notion of sense is unrelated to Husserl s noema while the latter s notions of meaning and object differ from those of Frege In detail Husserl s conception of logic and mathematics differs from that of Frege who held that arithmetic could be derived from logic For Husserl this is not the case mathematics with the exception of geometry is the ontological correlate of logic and while both fields are related neither one is strictly reducible to the other Husserl s criticism of psychologism Reacting against authors such as John Stuart Mill Christoph von Sigwart and his own former teacher Brentano Husserl criticised their psychologism in mathematics and logic i e their conception of these abstract and a priori sciences as having an essentially empirical foundation and a prescriptive or descriptive nature According to psychologism logic would not be an autonomous discipline but a branch of psychology either proposing a prescriptive and practical art of correct judgement as Brentano and some of his more orthodox students did or a description of the factual processes of human thought Husserl pointed out that the failure of anti psychologists to defeat psychologism was a result of being unable to distinguish between the foundational theoretical side of logic and the applied practical side Pure logic does not deal at all with thoughts or judgings as mental episodes but about a priori laws and conditions for any theory and any judgments whatsoever conceived as propositions in themselves Here Judgement has the same meaning as proposition understood not as a grammatical but as an ideal unity of meaning This is the case with all the distinctions of acts or forms of judgement which provide the foundations for the laws of pure logic Categorial hypothetical disjunctive existential judgements and however else we may call them in pure logic are not names for classes of judgements but for ideal forms of propositions Since truth in itself has being in itself as ontological correlate and since psychologists reduce truth and hence logic to empirical psychology the inevitable consequence is scepticism Psychologists have not been successful either in showing how induction or psychological processes can justify the absolute certainty of logical principles such as the principles of identity and non contradiction It is therefore futile to base certain logical laws and principles on uncertain processes of the mind This confusion made by psychologism and related disciplines such as biologism and anthropologism can be due to three specific prejudices The first prejudice is the supposition that logic is somehow normative in nature Husserl argues that logic is theoretical i e that logic itself proposes a priori laws which are themselves the basis of the normative side of logic Since mathematics is related to logic he cites an example from mathematics a formula like a b a b a b does not offer any insight into how to think mathematically It just expresses a truth A proposition that says The product of the sum and the difference of a and b should give the difference of the squares of a and b does express a normative proposition but this normative statement is based on the theoretical statement a b a b a b For psychologists the acts of judging reasoning deriving and so on are all psychological processes Therefore it is the role of psychology to provide the foundation of these processes Husserl states that this effort made by psychologists is a metabasis eis allo genos Ancient Greek metabasis eἰs ἄllo genos lit a transgression to another field 344 It is a metabasis because psychology cannot provide any foundations for a priori laws which themselves are the basis for all correct thought Psychologists have the problem of confusing intentional activities with the object of these activities It is important to distinguish between the act of judging and the judgment itself the act of counting and the number itself and so on Counting five objects is undeniably a psychological process but the number 5 is not Judgments can be true or not true Psychologists argue that judgments are true because they become evidently true to us 261 This evidence a psychological process that guarantees truth is indeed a psychological process Husserl responds by saying that truth itself as well as logical laws always remain valid regardless of psychological evidence that they are true No psychological process can explain the a priori objectivity of these logical truths From this criticism to psychologism the distinction between psychological acts and their intentional objects and the difference between the normative side of logic and the theoretical side derives from a Platonist conception of logic This means that logical and mathematical laws should be regarded as being independent of the human mind and also as an autonomy of meanings It is essentially the difference between the real everything subject to time and the ideal or irreal everything that is atemporal such as logical truths mathematical entities mathematical truths and meanings in general InfluenceHusserl s gravestone at Gunterstal David Carr commented on Husserl following in his 1970 dissertation at Yale It is well known that Husserl was always disappointed at the tendency of his students to go their own way to embark upon fundamental revisions of phenomenology rather than engage in the communal task as originally intended by the radical new science Notwithstanding he did attract philosophers to phenomenology Martin Heidegger is the best known of Husserl s students the one whom Husserl chose as his successor at Freiburg Heidegger s magnum opus Being and Time was dedicated to Husserl They shared their thoughts and worked alongside each other for over a decade at the University of Freiburg Heidegger being Husserl s assistant during 1920 1923 Heidegger s early work followed his teacher but with time he began to develop new insights distinctively variant Husserl became increasingly critical of Heidegger s work especially in 1929 and included pointed criticism of Heidegger in lectures he gave during 1931 Heidegger while acknowledging his debt to Husserl followed a political position offensive and harmful to Husserl after the Nazis came to power in 1933 Husserl being of Jewish origin and Heidegger infamously being then a Nazi proponent Academic discussion of Husserl and Heidegger is extensive At Gottingen in 1913 Adolf Reinach 1884 1917 was now Husserl s right hand He was above all the mediator between Husserl and the students for he understood extremely well how to deal with other persons whereas Husserl was pretty much helpless in this respect He was an original editor of Husserl s new journal Jahrbuch one of his works giving a phenomenological analysis of the law of obligations appeared in its first issue Reinach was widely admired and a remarkable teacher Husserl in his 1917 obituary wrote He wanted to draw only from the deepest sources he wanted to produce only work of enduring value And through his wise restraint he succeeded in this Edith Stein was Husserl s student at Gottingen and Freiburg while she wrote her doctoral thesis The Empathy Problem as it Developed Historically and Considered Phenomenologically 1916 She then became his assistant at Freiburg in 1916 18 She later adapted her phenomenology to the modern school of modern Thomism Ludwig Landgrebe became assistant to Husserl in 1923 From 1939 he collaborated with Eugen Fink at the Husserl Archives in Leuven In 1954 he became leader of the Husserl Archives Landgrebe is known as one of Husserl s closest associates but also for his independent views relating to history religion and politics as seen from the viewpoints of existentialist philosophy and metaphysics Eugen Fink was a close associate of Husserl during the 1920s and 1930s He wrote the Sixth Cartesian Meditation which Husserl said was the truest expression and continuation of his own work Fink delivered the eulogy for Husserl in 1938 Roman Ingarden an early student of Husserl at Freiburg corresponded with Husserl into the mid 1930s Ingarden did not accept however the later transcendental idealism of Husserl which he thought would lead to relativism Ingarden has written his work in German and Polish In his Spor o istnienie swiata Ger Der Streit um die Existenz der Welt Eng Dispute about existence of the world he created his own realistic position which also helped to spread phenomenology in Poland Max Scheler met Husserl in Halle in 1901 and found in his phenomenology a methodological breakthrough for his own philosophy Scheler who was at Gottingen when Husserl taught there was one of the original few editors of the journal Jahrbuch fur Philosophie und Phanomenologische Forschung 1913 Scheler s work Formalism in Ethics and Nonformal Ethics of Value appeared in the new journal 1913 and 1916 and drew acclaim The personal relationship between the two men however became strained due to Scheler s legal troubles and Scheler returned to Munich Although Scheler later criticised Husserl s idealistic logical approach and proposed instead a phenomenology of love he states that he remained deeply indebted to Husserl throughout his work Nicolai Hartmann was once thought to be at the center of phenomenology but perhaps no longer In 1921 the prestige of Hartmann the Neo Kantian who was Professor of Philosophy at Marburg was added to the Movement he publicly declared his solidarity with the actual work of die Phanomenologie Yet Hartmann s connections were with Max Scheler and the Munich circle Husserl himself evidently did not consider him as a phenomenologist His philosophy however is said to include an innovative use of the method Emmanuel Levinas in 1929 gave a presentation at one of Husserl s last seminars in Freiburg Also that year he wrote on Husserl s Ideen 1913 a long review published by a French journal With Gabrielle Peiffer Levinas translated into French Husserl s Meditations cartesiennes 1931 He was at first impressed with Heidegger and began a book on him but broke off the project when Heidegger became involved with the Nazis After the war he wrote on Jewish spirituality most of his family had been murdered by the Nazis in Lithuania Levinas then began to write works that would become widely known and admired Alfred Schutz s Phenomenology of the Social World seeks to rigorously ground Max Weber s interpretive sociology in Husserl s phenomenology Husserl was impressed by this work and asked Schutz to be his assistant Jean Paul Sartre was also largely influenced by Husserl although he later came to disagree with key points in his analyses Sartre rejected Husserl s transcendental interpretations begun in his Ideen 1913 and instead followed Heidegger s ontology Maurice Merleau Ponty s Phenomenology of Perception is influenced by Edmund Husserl s work on perception intersubjectivity intentionality space and temporality including Husserl s theory of retention and protention Merleau Ponty s description of motor intentionality and sexuality for example retain the important structure of the noetic noematic correlation of Ideen I yet further concretize what it means for Husserl when consciousness particularizes itself into modes of intuition Merleau Ponty s most clearly Husserlian work is perhaps the Philosopher and His Shadow Depending on the interpretation of Husserl s accounts of eidetic intuition given in Husserl s Phenomenological Psychology and Experience and Judgment it may be that Merleau Ponty did not accept the eidetic reduction nor the pure essence said to result Merleau Ponty was the first student to study at the Husserl archives in Leuven Gabriel Marcel explicitly rejected existentialism due to Sartre but not phenomenology which has enjoyed a wide following among French Catholics He appreciated Husserl Scheler and but with apprehension Heidegger His expressions like ontology of sensability when referring to the body indicate influence by phenomenological thought Kurt Godel is known to have read Cartesian Meditations He expressed very strong appreciation for Husserl s work especially with regard to bracketing or epoche Hermann Weyl s interest in intuitionistic logic and impredicativity appears to have resulted from his reading of Husserl He was introduced to Husserl s work through his wife Helene Joseph herself a student of Husserl at Gottingen Colin Wilson has used Husserl s ideas extensively in developing his New Existentialism particularly in regards to his intentionality of consciousness which he mentions in a number of his books Rudolf Carnap was also influenced by Husserl not only concerning Husserl s notion of essential insight that Carnap used in his Der Raum but also his notion of formation rules and transformation rules is founded on Husserl s philosophy of logic Karol Wojtyla who would later become Pope John Paul II was influenced by Husserl Phenomenology appears in his major work The Acting Person 1969 Originally published in Polish it was translated by Andrzej Potocki and edited by Anna Teresa Tymieniecka in the Analecta Husserliana The Acting Person combines phenomenological work with Thomistic ethics Plaque commemorating Husserl in his home town of Prostejov Czech Republic Paul Ricœur has translated many works of Husserl into French and has also written many of his own studies of the philosopher Among other works Ricœur employed phenomenology in his Freud and Philosophy 1965 Jacques Derrida wrote several critical studies of Husserl early in his academic career These included his dissertation The Problem of Genesis in Husserl s Philosophy and also his introduction to The Origin of Geometry Derrida continued to make reference to Husserl in works such as Of Grammatology Stanislaw Lesniewski and Kazimierz Ajdukiewicz were inspired by Husserl s formal analysis of language Accordingly they employed phenomenology in the development of categorial grammar Jose Ortega y Gasset visited Husserl at Freiburg in 1934 He credited phenomenology for having liberated him from a narrow neo Kantian thought While perhaps not a phenomenologist himself he introduced the philosophy to Iberia and Latin America Wilfrid Sellars an influential figure in the so called Pittsburgh School Robert Brandom John McDowell had been a student of Marvin Farber a pupil of Husserl and was influenced by phenomenology through him Marvin Farber led me through my first careful reading of the Critique of Pure Reason and introduced me to Husserl His combination of utter respect for the structure of Husserl s thought with the equally firm conviction that this structure could be given a naturalistic interpretation was undoubtedly a key influence on my own subsequent philosophical strategy In his 1942 essay The Myth of Sisyphus absurdist philosopher Albert Camus acknowledges Husserl as a previous philosopher who described and attempted to deal with the feeling of the absurd but claims he committed philosophical suicide by elevating reason and ultimately arriving at ubiquitous Platonic forms and an abstract god Hans Blumenberg received his habilitation in 1950 with a dissertation on ontological distance an inquiry into the crisis of Husserl s phenomenology Roger Scruton despite some disagreements with Husserl drew upon his work in 1986 3 4 The influence of the Husserlian phenomenological tradition in the 21st century extends beyond the confines of the European and North American legacies It has already started to impact indirectly scholarship in Eastern and Oriental thought including research on the impetus of philosophical thinking in the history of ideas in Islam BibliographyIn German 1887 Uber den Begriff der Zahl Psychologische Analysen On the Concept of Number habilitation thesis 1891 Philosophie der Arithmetik Psychologische und logische Untersuchungen Philosophy of Arithmetic 1900 Logische Untersuchungen Erster Teil Prolegomena zur reinen Logik Logical Investigations Vol 1 Prolegomena to Pure Logic 1901 Logische Untersuchungen Zweiter Teil Untersuchungen zur Phanomenologie und Theorie der Erkenntnis Logical Investigations Vol 2 1911 Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft included in Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy Philosophy as Rigorous Science and Philosophy and the Crisis of European Man 1913 Ideen zu einer reinen Phanomenologie und phanomenologischen Philosophie Erstes Buch Allgemeine Einfuhrung in die reine Phanomenologie Ideas General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology 1923 24 Erste Philosophie Zweiter Teil Theorie der phanomenologischen Reduktion First Philosophy Vol 2 Phenomenological Reductions 1925 Erste Philosophie Erster Teil Kritische Ideengeschichte First Philosophy Vol 1 Critical History of Ideas 1928 Vorlesungen zur Phanomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins Lectures on the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time 1929 Formale und transzendentale Logik Versuch einer Kritik der logischen Vernunft Formal and Transcendental Logic 1930 Nachwort zu meinen Ideen zu einer reinen Phanomenologie und phanomenologischen Philosophie Postscript to my Ideas 1936 Die Krisis der europaischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phanomenologie Eine Einleitung in die phanomenologische Philosophie The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy 1939 Erfahrung und Urteil Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik Experience and Judgment 1950 Cartesianische Meditationen translation of Meditations cartesiennes Cartesian Meditations 1931 1952 Ideen II Phanomenologische Untersuchungen zur Konstitution Ideas II Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution 1952 Ideen III Die Phanomenologie und die Fundamente der Wissenschaften Ideas III Phenomenology and the Foundations of the Sciences 1973 Zur Phanomenologie der Intersubjektivitat On the Phenomenology of Intersubjectivity In English Philosophy of Arithmetic Willard Dallas trans 2003 1891 Dordrecht Kluwer Logical Investigations 1973 1900 2nd revised edition 1913 Findlay J N trans London Routledge Philosophy as Rigorous Science translated in Quentin Lauer S J editor 1965 1910 Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy New York Harper amp Row Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy First Book General Introduction to a Pure Phenomenology 1982 1913 Kersten F trans The Hague Nijhoff Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy Second Book Studies in the Phenomenology of Constitution 1989 R Rojcewicz and A Schuwer translators Dordrecht Kluwer Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology and to a Phenomenological Philosophy Third Book Phenomenology and the Foundations of the Sciences 1980 Klein T E and Pohl W E translators Dordrecht Kluwer On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time 1893 1917 1990 1928 Brough J B trans Dordrecht Kluwer Cartesian Meditations 1960 1931 Cairns D trans Dordrecht Kluwer Formal and Transcendental Logic 1969 1929 Cairns D trans The Hague Nijhoff Experience and Judgement 1973 1939 Churchill J S and Ameriks K translators London Routledge The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology 1970 1936 54 Carr D trans Evanston Northwestern University Press Universal Teleology Telos 4 Fall 1969 New York Telos Press Anthologies Willard Dallas trans 1994 Early Writings in the Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics Dordrecht Kluwer Welton Donn ed 1999 The Essential Husserl Bloomington Indiana University Press See alsoEarly phenomenology Experimental phenomenology List of phenomenologistsNotesHusserl is mentioned by Bernard Stiegler in the 2004 film The Ister Citations Husserl Collins English Dictionary HarperCollins Retrieved 24 August 2019 Husserl Dictionary com Husserl The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language 5th ed HarperCollins Retrieved 24 August 2019 Husserl Merriam Webster com Dictionary Merriam Webster Retrieved 24 August 2019 Krech Eva Maria Stock Eberhard Hirschfeld Ursula Anders Lutz Christian 2009 Deutsches Ausspracheworterbuch German Pronunciation Dictionary in German Berlin Walter de Gruyter pp 465 598 ISBN 978 3 11 018202 6 Smith D W 2007 Husserl p xiv Cooper Wiele J K 6 December 2012 The Totalizing Act Key to Husserl s Early Philosophy Springer Science amp Business Media ISBN 978 94 009 2259 4 Kockelmans Joseph J Kisiel Theodore J 1970 Phenomenology and the Natural Sciences Essays and Translations Northwestern University Press p 3 ISBN 978 0 8101 0613 0 Joseph J Kockelmans Biographical Note per Edmund Husserl at 17 20 in his edited Phenomenology The Philosophy of Edmund Husserl and Its Interpretation Garden City NY Doubleday Anchor 1967 Husserl Page Husserl s Biography in Brief Husserlpage com Retrieved 28 July 2023 Spiegelberg H The Phenomenological Movement A historical introduction The Hague Martinus Nijhoff 2d ed ISBN 9024702399 Vol I pp 85 87 It was reported from witnesses of Husserl s last days that Husserl had something like a deathbed conversion Spiegelberg 1971 at I 85 Spiegelberg E 9 March 2013 The Context of the Phenomenological Movement Springer Science amp Business Media p 134 ISBN 978 94 017 3270 3 Kockelmans Biographical Note per Edmund Husserl 17 20 at 17 18 in his edited Phenomenology Doubleday Anchor 1967 Husserl s Philosophie der Arithmetik is further discussed here below Gerhart Husserl by H Pallard and R Hudson Archived from the original on 7 February 2005 Cf Illustrative extracts from Frege s Review of Husserl s Philosophie der Arithmetik translated by P T Geach at 79 85 in Peter Geach and Max Black editors Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege Oxford Basil Blackwell 1977 Beyer Christian 2022 Zalta Edward N Nodelman Uri eds Edmund Husserl The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2022 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 26 February 2025 What the exact impact this criticism by Frege may have had on Husserl s subsequent positions is the subject of debate See below herein the section Husserl and the Critique of Psychologism and the subsection Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics Husserl s Logische in its disentangling of psychology from logic also served as preparation for the later development of his work in phenomenological reduction Marvin Farber Husserl and Philosophical Radicalism The ideas of a presuppositionless philosophy 37 57 at 47 48 in Kockelmans ed Phenomenology 1967 Ricoeur Paul December 1967 29 30 Husserl An Analysis of His Phenomenology Northwestern University Press ISBN 978 0 8101 0530 0 Ricœur traces Husserl s development from the Logische Untersuchungen to his later Ideen Ideas 1913 as leading from the psychological to the transcendental regarding the intuition of essences which the methodology of the phenomenological reduction allows The book Husserl contains translations of Ricœur s essays of 1949 1967 Husserl Vorlesungen zur Phanomenologie des inneren Zeitbewusstseins 1928 translated as The Phenomenology of Internal Time Consciousness Indiana University 1964 Husserl Ideen au einer reinen Phanomenologie und phanomenologischen Philosophie 1913 translated as Ideas General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology New York Macmillan 1931 reprint Collier with Author s Preface to the English Edition at 5 22 Therein Husserl in 1931 refers to Transcendental Subjectivity being a new field of experience opened as a result of practicing phenomenological reduction and giving rise to an a priori science not empirically based but somewhat similar to mathematics By such practice the individual becomes the transcendental Ego although Husserl acknowledges the problem of solipsism Later he emphasizes the necessary stressing of the difference between transcendental and psychological subjectivity the repeated declaration that transcendental phenomenology is not in any sense psychology but rather in contrast to naturalistic psychology by the phenomenological reduction the life of the soul is made intelligible in its most intimate and originally intuitional essence and whereby objects of the most varied grades right up to the level of the objective world are there for the Ego Ibid at 5 7 11 12 18 Ricoeur Paul 1967 Husserl An Analysis of His Phenomenology p 33 In his Ideen period 1911 1925 Husserl also produced two unpublished manuscripts later referred to as Ideen II and Ideen III Ricœur 1967 at 35 Jean Paul Sartre La Transcendance de L Ego Esquisse d une description phenomenologique in Recherches Philosophiques VI 1937 translated as The Transcendence of the Ego An existentialist theory of consciousness New York The Noonday Press 1957 Sartre s disagreement with Husserl seems to have facilitated the transition from phenomenology to the existentialist doctrines of L Etre et le Neant 1943 F Williams and R Kirkpatrick Translator s introduction 11 27 at 12 to Transcendence of the Ego 1957 Ricoeur Paul 1967 Husserl An Analysis of His Phenomenology Northwestern University pp 29 30 cf 177 178 Husserl Ideen 1913 translated as Ideas 1931 e g at 161 165 Ricoeur Husserl 1967 at 25 27 Ideen does not address the problem of solipsism Ricœur 1967 at 31 Peter Koestenbaum Introductory Essay ix lxxvii at lxxv in Husserl The Paris Lectures The Hague Martinus Nijhoff 2d ed 1967 In the 1962 translation Being and Time by Macquarrie and Robinson Heidegger states Dedicated to Edmund Husserl in friendship and admiration Todnauberg in Baden Black Forest 8 April 1926 Edmund Husserl Pariser Vortrage 1929 translated as The Paris Lectures The Hague Martinus Nijhoff 2d ed 1967 by Peter Koestenbaum with an Introductory Essay at ix lxxvii This work was published first in French Husserl Meditations cartesiennes Paris Armand Colin 1931 translated by Gabrielle Peiffer and Emmanuel Levinas A German edition Cartesianische Meditationen which Husserl had reworked came out in 1950 Ricoeur Paul 1967 Husserl An Analysis of His Phenomenology Northwestern University pp 82 85 115 116 123 142 Ricoeur wonders whether here Husserl does not square the circle regarding the issue of solipsism Zack Naomi September 2009 The Handy Philosophy Answer Book Visible Ink Press pp 273 274 ISBN 978 1 57859 277 7 Husserl Die Krisis der europaischen Wissenschaften und die transzendentale Phanomenologie Belgrade 1936 As a Jew who was denied any public platform in Germany Husserl had to publish as he had lectured outside his own country Philosophia in Belgrade began its publication David Carr Translator s Introduction xv xliii at xvii to Edmund Husserl The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology Northwestern University 1970 Quentin Lauer Introduction pp 1 68 at pp 6 7 in Edmund Husserl Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy New York Harper amp Row Torchbook 1965 translated are two works by Husserl the 1935 Prague lecture Philosophy and the Crisis of European Man Philosophie und die Krisis des europaischen Menschentums and the 1911 essay Philosophy as Rigorous Science Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft Carr David 1970 Translator s Introduction xv xliii at xxx xxxi xxxiv xxxv xxxvii xxxviii historicism xxxvi xxxvii as given to Husserl The Crises of European Sciences Ricœur Paul 1949 Husserl et le sens de l histoire as translated in his Husserl An Analysis of His Phenomenology 1967 at pp 143 174 Husserl The Crises of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology Northwestern University 1970 e g at 127 Carr David 1970 Translator s Introduction xv xliii at xxxviii xlii to Husserl The Crises of European Sciences Beyer Christian 2022 Zalta Edward N Nodelman Uri eds Edmund Husserl The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2022 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 26 February 2025 Hugo Ott Martin Heidegger Unterwegs zu seiner Biographie Campus Verlag p 168 Walter Biemel Erinnerungsfragmente in Erinnerung an Martin Heidegger Neske 1977 S 22 Rudiger Safranski Martin Heidegger Between Good and Evil Cambridge Mass amp London Harvard University Press 1998 pp 253 8 Spiegelberg Herbert 1971 The Phenomenological Movement A historical introduction The Hague Martinus Nijhoff 2d ed ISBN 9024702399 Vol I pp 281 283 Around this time Husserl also began to refer to Heidegger and Scheler as his philosophical antipodes Spiegelberg 1970 at p 283 Husserl Edmund 1997 Psychological and Transcendental Phenomenology and the Confrontation with Heidegger 1927 1931 translated by T Sheehan and R Palmer Dordrecht Kluwer ISBN 0792344812 which contains his Phanomenologie und Anthropologie at pp 485 500 Nur noch ein Gott kann uns retten Der Spiegel 31 May 1967 Richard Evans The Coming of the Third Reich Penguin 2003 p 421 Cf Peter Koestenbaum Introductory Essay ix lxxvii at lxxv lxxvi in his edited Edmund Husserl The Paris Lectures The Hague Martinus Nijhoff 2d ed 1967 His widow Malvine Husserl was instrumental in this rescue project she became a convert to Catholicism in 1941 Kockelmans The Husserl Archives at 20 21 in his edited Phenomenology Doubleday Anchor 1967 Philosophy from an Empirical Standpoint Essays on Carl Stumpf BRILL 2 June 2015 p 159 ISBN 978 90 04 29910 8 Simons Peter Parts A Study in Ontology Oxford University Press Chisholm R M 1967 Intentionality The Encyclopedia of Philosophy 4 201 Warren Nicolas de 5 November 2009 Husserl and the Promise of Time Subjectivity in Transcendental Phenomenology Cambridge University Press p 79 ISBN 978 0 521 87679 7 Boer Theodorus A de 31 December 1978 The Development of Husserl s Thought Springer p 121 ISBN 978 90 247 2039 2 Retrieved 18 April 2013 This assumption led Husserl to an idealistic position which he originally had tried to overcome or avoid On Husserl s phenomenological idealism see Hans Kochler Die Subjekt Objekt Dialektik in der transzendentalen Phanomenologie Das Seinsproblem zwischen Idealismus und Realismus Monographien zur philosophischen Forschung Vol 112 Meisenheim a G Anton Hain 1974 Crisis of European Humanity Pt II 1935 Ralph Keen 24 November 2009 Exile and Restoration in Jewish Thought An Essay in Interpretation Continuum p 68 ISBN 978 0 8264 5308 2 Retrieved 21 December 2012 Edmund Husserl Ideas General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology tr W R Boyce Gibson New York Macmillan 1962 96 103 155 67 Husserl Ideas 194 Husserl Ideas 242 43 Husserl Ideas 105 109 Mark P Drost The Primacy of Perception in Husserl s Theory of Imagining PPR 1 1990 569 82 The German begreifen cognate with English grip carries the same sense Burgin Mark 27 October 2016 Theory Of Knowledge Structures And Processes World Scientific p 468 ISBN 978 981 4522 69 4 Hill Claire Ortiz Haddock Guillermo E Rosado 2000 Husserl Or Frege Meaning Objectivity and Mathematics Open Court Publishing p 35 ISBN 978 0 8126 9417 8 Dahlstrom D O 2004 Ontology New Catholic Encyclopedia Gale Sandkuhler Hans Jorg 2010 Ontologie Enzyklopadie Philosophie Meiner Archived from the original on 11 March 2021 Retrieved 22 December 2020 Gander Hans Helmuth 2009 Ontologie Husserl Lexikon Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft Follesdal Dagfinn 2006 Husserl s Reductions and the Role They Play in His Phenomenology A Companion to Phenomenology and Existentialism John Wiley amp Sons pp 105 114 doi 10 1002 9780470996508 ch8 ISBN 978 0 470 99650 8 Drummond John J 2009 Formal ontology Historical Dictionary of Husserl s Philosophy Scarecrow Poli Roberto 1993 Husserl s Conception of Formal Ontology History and Philosophy of Logic 14 1 14 doi 10 1080 01445349308837207 Moran Dermot Cohen Joseph 2012 Regional ontology The Husserl Dictionary Continuum Drummond John J 2009 Eidetic variation Historical Dictionary of Husserl s Philosophy Scarecrow Spear Andrew D Husserl Edmund Intentionality and Intentional Content Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 22 December 2020 Klein Jacob 22 April 2013 Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra Courier Corporation ISBN 978 0 486 31981 0 Alfred Schramm Meinongian Issues in Contemporary Italian Philosophy Walter de Gruyter 2009 p 28 Consider Jitendra Nath Mohanty 1995 The Development of Husserl s Thought in Barry Smith and David Woodruff Smith eds The Cambridge Companion to Husserl Cambridge University Press For further commentaries on the review see Willard Dallas 1984 Logic and the Objectivity of Knowledge Athens OH Ohio University Press p 63 J Philip Miller 1982 Numbers in Presence and Absence Phaenomenologica 90 Den Haag Nijhoff p 19 ff and Jitendra Nath Mohanty 1984 Husserl Frege and the Overcoming of Psychologism in Cho Kay Kyung ed Philosophy and Science in Phenomenological Perspective Phaenomenologica 95 Dordrecht Boston Lancaster Nijhoff p 145 Hill Claire Ortiz Haddock Guillermo E Rosado 2000 Husserl Or Frege Meaning Objectivity and Mathematics Open Court Publishing pp 253 262 ISBN 978 0 8126 9417 8 Husserl Chronik pp 25 26 Golomb Jacob 1976 Psychology from the Phenomenological Standpoint of Husserl Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 4 451 471 doi 10 2307 2106865 ISSN 0031 8205 JSTOR 2106865 See the quotes in Carlo Ierna Husserl s Critique of Double Judgments in Filip Mattens editor Meaning and Language Phenomenological Perspectives Phaenomenologica 187 Dordrecht Boston London Springer 2008 pp 50 f Edmund Husserl Logical Investigations volume 1 edited by Dermot Moran trans by J N Findlay New York Routledge 2001 p 112 Gutland Christopher 15 April 2019 Denk Erfahrung Eine phanomenologisch orientierte Untersuchung der Erfahrbarkeit des Denkens und der Gedanken in German Verlag Karl Alber p 344 ISBN 978 3 495 81759 9 Drummond J J 6 December 2012 Husserlian Intentionality and Non Foundational Realism Noema and Object Springer Science amp Business Media p 261 ISBN 978 94 009 1974 7 Carr David 1970 Translator s Introduction xv xlii at xxv to Edmund Husserl The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology Northwestern University Press Kockelmans Introduction Martin Heidegger 267 276 273 in Kockelmans editor Phenomenology 1967 Beyer Christian 23 August 2017 Edmund Husserl In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Heidegger was at Marburg 1923 1925 See above subsection Heidegger and the Nazi era The multivalent including the horrifying aspects of Heidegger in a parallel context are recounted in Peter Eli Gordon Rosensweig and Heidegger Between Judaism and German Philosophy University of California 2003 at 13 14 Heidegger and Rosensweig s early kinship with him In 1929 however one could still read Heidegger s philosophy without being drawn into a controversy concerning its relationship to National Socialism antisemitism and the like The German philosophical world as a whole still cloaked itself in a mantle of relative innocence Gordon 2003 at 303 304 Rosensweig s work represents the culmination of what is often called the German Jewish Tradition Gordon Preface 2003 at xix Edith Stein Reinach as a Philosophical Personality Selection from her memoirs xxvii xxix at xxvii in Aletheia III 1985 Adolf Reinach Die apriorischen Grundlagen des burgerlichen Rechtes in Jahrbuch fur Philosophie und phanomenologische Forschung I 685 847 1913 translated as The A Priori Foundation of Civil Law in Aletheia III 1 142 1983 Edmund Husserl Reinach as a Philosophical Personality Obituary notice xi xiv at xi in Aletheia III 1985 Waltraud Herbstrith Edith Stein A Biography New York Harper and Row 1985 1971 pp 13 14 24 42 44 John Raphael Staude Max Scheler New York Free Press 1967 at 19 20 27 28 Spiegelberg Herbert 1971 The Phenomenological Movement pp 258 259 371 Scheler 379 384 use of method Unsigned Preface at vii x to Emmanuel Levinas Basic philosophical writings Indiana University 1996 edited by Adriaan Peperzak Simon Critchley and Robert Bernasconi George Walsh Introduction Alfred Schutz The Phenomenology of the Social World Illinois 1997 p xviii Sartre The Transcendent of the Ego An Existentialist Theory of Consciousness 1937 New York Noonday 1957 See for example the influence of Husserl on Merleau Ponty s conception of l espace as expounded in Nader El Bizri A Phenomenological Account of the Ontological Problem of Space Existentia Meletai Sophias 12 2002 pp 345 364 Lectures Summer Semester 1925 Remy C Kwant Merleau Ponty s Criticism of Husserl s Eidetic Reduction in Joseph J Kochelmans Phenomenology The Philosophy of Edmund Husserl and its Interpretation Garden City NY Doubleday Anchor 1967 at 393 408 394 395 404 405 Spiegelberg Herbert and Schuhmann Karl 1982 The Phenomenological Movement Springer pp 438 439 448 449 Caponigri A Robert 1971 A History of Western Philosophy University of Notre Dame Vol V pp 284 285 Colin Wilson 1966 Introduction to the New Existentialism Ashgate Publishing p 54 ISBN 978 0 7045 0415 8 Smith D W and Thomasson Amie L eds 2005 Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind Oxford and New York Oxford University Press p 8 n 18 Wojtyla Karol 2002 The Acting Person A Contribution to Phenomenological Anthropology Springer ISBN 90 277 0985 8 Cf Paul Ricœur Husserl An analysis of his phenomenology Northwestern University 1967 collected essays translated Ricœur Freud and Philosophy An essay in interpretation 1965 Yale University 1970 Cf Smith Barry 1989 On the Origins of Analytic Philosophy PDF Grazer Philosophische Studien vol 34 pp 153 173 Spiegelberg Herbert and Schuhmann Karl 1982 The Phenomenological Movement Springer pp 658 659 Sellars Wilfrid 1975 Autobiographical Reflections in Castaneda Hector Neri ed Action Knowledge and Reality Critical Studies in Honor of Wilfrid Sellars Indianapolis Bobbs Merrill Scruton Roger 1994 Sexual Desire A Philosophical Investigation London Phoenix pp 3 4 ISBN 1 85799 100 1 See for instance Nader El Bizri The Phenomenological Quest Between Avicenna and Heidegger Binghamton N Y Global Publications SUNY at Binghamton 2000 and also refer to Nader El Bizri Avicenna s De Anima between Aristotle and Husserl in The Passions of the Soul in the Metamorphosis of Becoming ed Anna Teresa Tymieniecka Dordrecht Kluwer Academic Publishers 2003 pp 67 89 Islamic Philosophy and Occidental Phenomenology in Dialogue Springer Retrieved 26 February 2025 Cite error A list defined reference named IEPHusserl is not used in the content see the help page Further readingAdorno Theodor W 2013 Against Epistemology Cambridge Polity Press ISBN 978 0745665382 Bernet Rudolf et al 1993 Introduction to Husserlian Phenomenology Evanston Northwestern University Press ISBN 0 8101 1030 X Derrida Jacques 1954 French 2003 English The Problem of Genesis in Husserl s Philosophy Chicago amp London University of Chicago Press 1962 French 1976 English Introduction to Husserl s The Origin of Geometry Includes Derrida s translation of Appendix III of Husserl s 1936 The Crisis of European Sciences and Transcendental Phenomenology 1967 French 1973 English Speech and Phenomena La Voix et le Phenomene and other Essays on Husserl s Theory of Signs ISBN 0 8101 0397 4 Fink Eugen 1995 Sixth Cartesian meditation The Idea of a Transcendental Theory of Method with textual notations by Edmund Husserl Translated with an introduction by Ronald Bruzina Bloomington Indiana University Press Hill C O 1991 Word and Object in Husserl Frege and Russell The Roots of Twentieth Century Philosophy Ohio Univ Press Hopkins Burt C 2011 The Philosophy of Husserl Durham Acumen Levinas Emmanuel 1963 French 1973 English The Theory of Intuition in Husserl s Phenomenology Evanston Northwestern University Press Kochler Hans 1982 Edmund Husserl s Theory of Meaning The Hague Martinus Nijhoff 1982 Husserl and Frege Bloomington Indiana University Press Moran D and Cohen J 2012 The Husserl Dictionary London Continuum Press Natanson Maurice 1973 Edmund Husserl Philosopher of Infinite Tasks Evanston Northwestern University Press ISBN 0 8101 0425 3 Ortiz Hill Claire da Silva Jairo Jose eds 1997 The Road Not Taken On Husserl s Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics College Publications Ricœur Paul 1967 Husserl An Analysis of His Phenomenology Evanston Northwestern University Press Rollinger R D 2008 Austrian Phenomenology Brentano Husserl Meinong and Others on Mind and Language Frankfurt am Main Ontos Verlag ISBN 978 3 86838 005 7 Sokolowski Robert Introduction to Phenomenology New York Cambridge University Press 1999 ISBN 978 0 521 66792 0 Smith B Smith D W eds 1995 The Cambridge Companion to Husserl Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 43616 8 Smith David Woodruff 2007 Husserl London Routledge Zahavi Dan 2003 Husserl s Phenomenology Stanford Stanford University Press ISBN 0 8047 4546 3External linksWikimedia Commons has media related to Edmund Husserl Wikiquote has quotations related to Edmund Husserl Library resources about Edmund Husserl Resources in your library Resources in other libraries Husserl archives Husserl Archives Leuven the main Husserl Archive in Leuven International Centre for Phenomenological Research Husserliana Edmund Husserl Gesammelte Werke the ongoing critical edition of Husserl s works Husserliana Materialien edition for lectures and shorter works Edmund Husserl Collected Works English translation of Husserl s works Husserl Archives at the University of Cologne Husserl Archives Freiburg Archives Husserl de Paris at the Ecole normale superieure Paris Works by or about Edmund Husserl at the Internet ArchiveOther links Beyer Christian Edmund Husserl In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Smith David Woodruff Phenomenology In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Papers on Edmund Husserl by Barry Smith English translation of Vienna Lecture 1935 Philosophy and the Crisis of European Humanity The Husserl Page by Bob Sandmeyer Includes a number of online texts in German and English Husserl net open content project Edmund Husserl Formal Ontology and Transcendental Logic Resource guide on Husserl s logic and formal ontology with annotated bibliography The Husserl Circle Cartesian Meditations in Internet Archive Ideas Part I in Internet Archive Edmund Husserl on the Open Commons of Phenomenology Complete bibliography and links to all German texts including Husserliana vols I XXVIII